capital
Race and Reification
This article uses Marx’s idea of commodity fetishism and subsequent theories of reification to understand the social-construction of race. Race is typically defined as a socially-constituted category that is misattributed as a natural one. The goal of this article, in contrast, is to explain how this misattribution arises. In addition to this main objective, the article uses this explanation of race to contest recent attempts that locate the ‘persistent entanglement’ of race and capital in their functional relationship. Finally, the article engages with related, commodity-based theories of race and racism and concludes with thoughts on what the socially-constructed category of race can teach us about the nature of value and capitalism.
This piece is being made available as a preprint edition of the Race and Capital special issue of Historical Materialism. The final published version of this text will be made available on the Brill website in the coming months, we ask that citations refer to the Brill edition.
Issue 32(2&3): Race and Capital
Introduction
Marxists often invoke class to help them understand race. [1][2] But this approach has always been met with considerable difficulty. Such a strategy typically has the character of subsuming race within class, in a way that inevitably fails to account for the distinctiveness of race—its autonomy. This article charts a different path and, instead of looking to class for insights into race, turns to capitalism in its most abstract form: value. Building on Marx’s theory of commodity fetishism and subsequent writings on reification and the form of value’s objectivity, the article explores the idea that the social relation between ‘things’ that comprises the world of commodities is also the objective form that socially constitutes race as an apparently unmediated natural or social fact. The popular social-constructionist approach to understanding race and racism, standardly defines race as a socially-constituted category that is misattributed as a self-sufficiently natural thing. The goal of this article, in contrast, is to explainhow this misattribution arises.
In his critique of political economy, Marx analyzes value, ‘something purely social,’[3] which emerges only within historically-specific social relations. These social relations are those of the ‘exchange society,’ where production is undertaken for the purpose of exchange, rather than need. Within these relations, value exists as a ‘thingly’ form of objectivity that obtains, with absolute social validity, a real independence and autonomy. However, this form of objectivity—the thingly existence that value attains within the practical activity of the producers—also creates the appearance that value is a natural property of the concrete, material ‘use values’ that are value’s bearers.
The nature of value also has broader, societal implications. In a world of generalised commodity production, the objectification of social relations as the misattributed natural properties of things generates a social world where relations between people are merely material, one populated by individuals where social outcomes are only aggregates of the characteristics of individuals. One consequence of this ‘asocial sociality’[4] is that the stratification of individuals by ‘race’ according to income, status, or location appears to derive from the attributes and traits of the individuals belonging to racialised groups. In reality, racism produces race, and yet the specifically historical and social factors that constitute race—colonialism, enslavement, discrimination, segregation, as well as the indifference of ‘colorblind’ capitalism—disappear in the value form’s objectivity along with the historically-specific social relations of value production themselves. Moreover, the objectivity of value not only naturalises race for the racist, but also constitutes race’s form as a fact for the non-racist observer. If the racist misattributes phenotype with a set of race-specific natural abilities or traits, the non-racist view reduces race to mere phenotype, shorn of any historical or social meaning. Furthermore, it should be stressed that the reification of race is not merely a subjective delusion; because the source of the epistemic error derives from the form of value’s objectivity itself, recognition of this may ‘destroy the semblance’ of the ‘accidental’ facticity of race, ‘but by no means abolishes that determination’s material form.’[5]
The concept of reification comes to us primarily from the work of Georg Lukács. In Lukács’ famous essay, ‘Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat,’ it is clear that he develops this concept out of an engagement with Marx’s theory of the fetishism of commodities. However, it is an open question how much reification is a concept fully developed by Marx or whether it owes more to the innovations of Lukács and others. Lukács’ analysis also relies greatly on both Weber and Simmel, just as much as on Marx, which may set his theory apart from Marx’s analysis of commodity fetishism. Members of the Frankfurt School also subsequently engaged with the concepts of fetishism and reification, in ways that further critique and refine the concept. Nevertheless, for the purposes of this article, these various refinements and subtleties need not preoccupy us. As the reader will see, this article relies primarily on Marx’s analysis of commodity fetishism for its explication of race as reification. We therefore do not need to be overly concerned with the concept’s subsequent evolution in the hands of Marx’s intellectual inheritors.
Nevertheless, this article will use the term ‘reification’ (meaning literally ‘thing-ification’) because it is simply a good, overarching description of the phenomenon under investigation, namely, the process by which abstract, historically-contingent social relations are turned into the natural or independent properties of things. In this article, the process we are concerned with is racialization, but similar processes occur in commodity fetishism and elsewhere. Indeed, using this broader term of ‘reification’ also acknowledges, like Lukács himself did, that the theory of commodity fetishism can be used not just in the critique of political economy, which was Marx’s primary concern inCapital, but also as the basis for a wider critical theory of society. Finally, using ‘reification’ discloses, forthrightly enough, that my reading of Marx’s theory of commodity fetishism has been informed by these subsequent thinkers in the tradition of critical theory, including contemporary theorists of social form such as Patrick Murray.[6]
The foregoing framing of the concept of reification will help situate the article among other studies of reification, including those that directly consider race. For example, Timothy Bewes’s wide-ranging cultural investigation of reification as ‘the anxiety of late capitalism’ has a far wider panoramic than the way reification is used in this article.[7] Perhaps for that reason, Bewes’s cultural analysis is also much less concerned either with the commodity structure of reification or the relationship between those phenomena and racial domination.[8] More related to this article is Joseph Gabel’s use of reification in what he describes as the ‘schizophrenic structure of racist ideology.’[9] However, unlike the notion of reification used in this article, which is closely tied to the fetishism of commodities, Gabel’s is far broader and, as he acknowledges, has no necessary connection to the commodity form, or even to capitalism. Gabel explains that ‘just as in psychopathology there can be a form of ‘reified consciousness’ unrelated to economic reification (schizophrenia), so also in sociology there can be (and indeed there are) forms of ‘reified consciousness’ which are linked to the conditions of existence so to speak without being in any way a reflection of a form of economic reification.’[10] Because one purpose of this article is to explore, in Nancy Fraser’s words, the ‘persistent entanglement’ of race and capital,[11] Gabel’s assertion that reification arises from the (universal) conditions of human existence is not free of problems, to put it mildly. Locating that persistent entanglement requires precisely that we view the reification of race as part of the value (or commodity) form’s fetishised objectivity found with capitalism, not a universal but a historically-specific form of production. Gabel’s unmooring of reification from commodity fetishism also essentially turns reification exclusively into an aspect of thought. Gabel’s explicit analysis reduces racism to the reified or schizophrenic psychology of the racist. Certainly, the social psychology of racist ideology undoubtedly constitutes an essential part of a much broader investigation of racial domination, and Gabel’s analysis contributes several interesting insights to this crucial component. However, a complete analysis of racial domination would also have to include the social psychology of the subjects of racial domination, as well as the historically-specific social conditions in which these psychologies arise. This article is concerned with the latter aim, and specifically with a critique of the subtle ontological and epistemological nature of the value form’s ‘false objectivity,’ which establishes just that social world in which racialised psychologies inhabit.[12]
A few other scholars have recently brought race and racism into conversation with the concept of ‘real abstraction,’ a concept which is closely related with the fetishism of commodities. However, at this stage, thinking of race as a real abstraction remains under-elaborated.[13] In the most important contribution to date, for example, Brenna Bhandar and Alberto Toscano catalogue several moments of abstraction. They write, ‘We would need to be able to think the articulation between events andprocesses of abstraction/dissolution … the ‘unconscious’ abstracting socialpractices … the high-levellogic of abstraction intrinsic to value as a social form of capitalism; and the relatively autonomous and deliberatepractices anddevices of abstraction.’[14] What Bhandar and Toscano, in addition to Alberto Toscano’s earlier contribution,[15] fruitfully offer us is an agenda for how we should think about race and racialization in contemporary capitalism. This article does not object to subscribing to race as a ‘real abstraction,’ in the sense of a conceptually-mediated, ‘mind-dependent’ social construction that has practical purchase in the social world. Just to that extent, however, ‘real abstraction’ would seem to be ubiquitous, even beyond one that would ‘tie[] the singularity of real abstraction to capitalism and capitalism alone.’[16] Moishe Postone clarifies for us that all social practice is conceptually mediated.[17] In his doctoral dissertation, Marx asks, ‘Didn’t the Moloch of the Ancients hold sway? Wasn’t the Delphic Apollo a real power in the life of the Greeks?’[18] Humans have always lived, worked, and died through abstraction. Real abstraction, however, at least in the theoretical tradition that I am most familiar with, is something other than this more quotidian and generic kind of abstraction. In this sense, real abstraction is the process by which labour becomes abstract through exchange (specifically,practically abstract[19]), ‘behind the backs’ of society’s members, a process that precedes their conscious awareness.[20] To emphasise, ‘race’ can certainly and productively be thought of as a ‘conceptuality [or abstraction] which holds sway in reality,’[21] that is, as that generic kind of conceptually-mediated social practice. As this article will also claim, the real abstraction of the value form plays a crucial role in the hypostatization of race as a ‘thing,’ without reducing the latter to the former. However, whether in the more restricted sense, as something which is only cognised post festum, race counts as a real abstraction is an extraordinarily interesting question, but one that space prohibits me from entertaining.
The article proceeds in the following order. This first part engages the central question of the article, posed in the introduction, and shows how the value form can explain the social construction of race and how race is misattributed as fact or nature. The second part of the article applies this explanation to the ongoing problem of the ‘persistent entanglement’ of race and capital. It argues that understanding race as a form of reification can avoid problematic functional approaches to race and class (or even capitalism) to which Marxist analyses often resort. Rather than approach the relationship between race and capital within a functional framework, viewing race as a form of reification grasps that relationship at an epistemological and ontological level.
There are surprisingly few investigations of race and reification. The third part of the article critically engages two of the best-known contributions, Moishe Postone’s analysis of Nazi antisemitism and Hylton White’s investigation of antiblack racism.[22] Both are remarkably insightful contributions which, like the present article, link racism with capitalism’s commodity structure. However, I question, first, what the racialised subjects of antisemitism and antiblack racism are said to represent and, second, exactly how capitalism’s abstract dimensions establish the ‘historical-epistemological frame of reference’[23] within which ‘race’ is practically and conceptually understood and produced. The article argues that the Jews or the black body do not represent abstract dimensions of capitalism (capital and labour, respectively), but rather that racialised attributes appear to have a thingly, pre-social existence because the abstract value-form hypostatises as natural or factual that which is actually social and historical.
Race and Reification
One of the most persistent ideological depictions involved in the production of race is the ‘naturalization’ frame. I take a broad view of ‘naturalization.’ Within this conception, a socially-constructed category, ‘race,’ is identified phenotypically but mistaken for fixed and immutable traits of the racialised grouping. In the extreme case, these traits are biological, as in nineteenth- and twentieth-century, ‘race science.’ More commonly today, these traits are said to be based not in biological but in no less invariant (and therefore, one could say, natural) ‘cultural’ differences.[24] In fact, the now predominant social-constructionist account of race would say that this naturalization frame defines what race is: ‘a symbolic category, based on phenotype or ancestry and constructed according to specific social and historical contexts, that is misrecognized as a natural category.’[25]
But we cannot be satisfied with a ‘definition’ of race as a misattributed natural category. We want to know why the naturalization of race is such a persistent ideological manifestation. Naturalization is not the only possible ideological construction of race. Historically, the naturalization frame has existed alongside religious and nationalist ones. This section of the article will propose that the theory of reification can explain why naturalization persists as the dominant ideological justification of race. As in the social-constructionist account, racism is a practice that produces race through a set of social relations. Adding to the social-constructionist account, this article will argue that the production of race as a misattributed natural kind is part of capitalism’s value form, a historically-specific form of objectivity and phenomenology.
I will first need to lay out what I will be calling the theory of reification. It begins with Marx’s account of the commodity and what he calls the fetishism surrounding it. A commodity has a dual character, comprised of both value and use value. The commodity’s concrete characteristics constitute its use value, its ability to satisfy some human want or need. A commodity is also a value, a product of human labour in the abstract, as distinguished from the concrete labour that produces particular use values. Marx calls abstract labour the substance of value. The magnitude of value—determined by the socially necessary labour time required for the commodity’s production—regulates the proportions at which commodities are exchanged when brought into relation with one another in the market. Value is a therefore a thoroughly social and—limited in time and place to a certain mode of production—historical category. However, the fetishism of commodities is that (like race) value does not present itself as a social and historical category.
There are both objective and subjective dimensions to the constitution of value. In its objective dimension, value is the objectified expression of the purely social characteristics of individual human labours undertaken privately. Marx calls this the ‘fetish character’ of the value form, ‘the essential determination consisting in the real inversion of human social powers as attributes of things.’[26] The objectivity of value is thus real, particularly in the sense that it has ‘social validity.’ This objectivity is autonomous, allowing the various, otherwise private and independent, producers to coordinate their activities (in a post hoc form) and which mediates the private labours of the various producers. Value is an objectified form of social mediation. However, it does not appear as mediated. Rather, in its subjective dimension, value appears to derive from the commodity’s character as use-value. Value, a ‘supra-natural property,’ ‘something purely social’ appears instead as a natural property of the use value, like its weight or color.[27] Marx calls this the ‘fetishism’ of the commodity, ‘the illusory consciousness that naturalises this social power of the commodity.’[28] Finally, the fetishism arises from the fetish character of the value form, ‘from the peculiar social character of the labour which produces’ commodities.[29] Because the specific social characteristics of labour only appear within exchange, the social relations between producers’ private labours ‘appear as what they are, … material [dinglich] relations between persons and social relations between things.’[30] The way that value is rendered thing-like through exchange—the way value in practice is objectified, through exchange, as an attribute of the use-values which are their bearers—makes it appear as an inherent property of the use values themselves.[31] One crucial dimension of this insight is that if the social relation between the producers and the sum total of their labour appears as a social relation between objects, ‘a relation which exists apart from and outside the producers,’ then the historically-specific nature of those social relations in which the value form exists will disappear.[32] This insight about the hypostatization of social relations is as true for race as it is for the value form, as we will shortly see.
Subsequent thinkers have generalised Marx’s insight, extending the theory of commodity fetishism to a critique not just of political economy and of the nature of value, but also of capitalist society. We can call this the theory of reification.[33] ‘[T]he problem of commodities must not be considered in isolation or even regarded as the central problem in economics,’ Georg Lukács famously wrote, ‘but as the central, structural problem of capitalist society in all its aspects.’[34] When Marx speaks of ‘material [dinglich] relations between persons and social relations between things’[35] he is referring as much to capitalist society as he is to the capitalist economy. With the universalization of exchange relations, the social, not just the ‘economic,’ world appears as a set of things: discrete, independent, even accidentally-related objects that can, in this form, be immediately apprehended, without requiring meaning, interpretation, or history. It is a world of reference rather than inference. This objective dimension is contrasted with a subjective one, characterised by abstract operations like logic and the attribution of properties and relations. Within this strict dichotomy between object and subject, the task of the social scientist is to subsume the concretely given and immediate objects of sense data under formally rational, abstract laws. Because of the thing-like form of objectivity, the social world takes on a ‘fragmented’ character, which imparts a subdivision and autonomy both to the various intellectual disciplines and the institutions of society, such as the state, the law, and the economy. Similar to Marx’s concerns, ‘Lukács’s starting point is the appearance of autonomy of the economy and, modeled on it, other apparently autonomous social institutions. Society appears as a collection of independent social ‘things’ ruled by the laws of the differentiated domains.’[36] The aim of Marx, Lukács, and other critical theorists is to not merely describe these facts, but to show that that ‘facticity is not a self-evident category. It must be constructed in the social world to which it is effectively relevant. This is the deepest function of the concept of reification. It is meant to explainhow the world can appear as a collection of facts.’[37]
One of these ‘facts’ is ‘race,’ and indeed the socially-constructed category of race exemplifies this process of reification at work. Racism, a set of social relations and practices, hypostatises race as a taken-for-granted, concrete and (or) natural fact.[38] On this the social constructionist and reification view agree. The task now is to demonstrate that the same process that hypostatises value as a thingly objectivity also accounts for the reification of race. Just as value appears as a natural attribute of the concrete use values which are their bearers, ‘race’ appears as the immutable or natural traits of the individual members of the racialised group. But this is not merely analogy: it is because a commodified, exchange society produces a peculiar kind of sociality (‘material relations between persons and social relations between things’) that the social and historical consequents of race appear as their causes.
Besides showing how value appears to be a pre-social, natural attribute of use-values, Marx extends his analysis of the fetishism of commodities to several other features of capitalist society. For example, money, a universally exchangeable commodity and the most general expression of value, underscores this same phenomenon.[39] Money, like any other commodity, appears to have value itself, ‘as a social property inherent in its nature,’[40] and so the social relation that money in fact expresses ‘vanishes in its own result, leaving no trace behind.’[41] As a consequence of this, money allows people to be ‘related to each other in their social process of production in a purely atomistic way.’[42]
To be clear, this is the way social relations actually operate in practice in capitalism, but it is also this practice that makes the social relation appear natural or material, rather than social.[43] But if the social relations of production appear material, then so does the socially-constructed category of race. To believe that people relate to one another in an atomistic way is to explain social outcomes in terms of the properties of the individuals themselves. Hence, if social outcomes are stratified by race, this must be—especially but not only in the reified mind of the racist—because of naturally-occurring traits held by members of the (in fact, socially constructed) ‘races.’ Because of money, Marx says that in capitalism the ‘individual carries his social power, as well as his bond with society, in his pocket.’[44] Consequently, we should not be surprised that, ‘if the knapsack of privileges is carried by an individual already identifiable as white,’ as described by Peggy McIntosh in her influential article ‘White Privilege: Unpacking the Invisible Knapsack,’ ‘then whiteness must necessarily be understood as a biological trait.’[45]
Marx’s broad application of commodity fetishism can also be grasped more sharply when recognizing that the attribution of value to use-values holds with greater significance for labour power and means of production. In the famous section on the ‘Trinity Formula,’ Marx contends that profits and wages appear to arise naturally from the material objects that bear them rather than from the social relations of the exchange society: on the one hand, means of production (‘capital,’ in the reified sense) and, on the other, the individual ability and intelligence of the individual wage-labourers. In fact, profits are a division from the ‘the total value of the annual product, which is nothing more than objectified social labour’[46]: profits come from exploited labour, not from the machines that labour uses. For the same reasons, if the income distribution is stratified by race this can be interpreted as a result not of de jure andde facto discrimination; a history of enslavement and expropriation; or the dynamics of profit accumulation, labour market stratification, and superfluous labour; but of the abilities and intelligence shared by members of a given ‘race.’[47]
Marx therefore extends his theory of commodity fetishism in his analysis of money, profits, and wages. By this, and numerous other indications, he also clearly intends this theory to have broader social and political implications. Scattered in various places, Marx urges us to recognise that bourgeois ‘individualism’ is not merely an ideological trope, legitimating discourse, or strategic manipulation.[48] Rather, it has a practical basis in the kind of ‘asocial sociality’[49] that exists in a society characterised by generalised commodity production, where relations between people are treated as merely material.[50] In this sort of society, social outcomes are perceived simply as the aggregates of individual choices, preferences, and capabilities—all properties of individuals.[51] Again, therefore, if social outcomes are stratified by races, these consequences are turned into their causes, and the social and natural are conflated by attributing them to natural or factual differences in ability at the racial level. To introduce past or present racism, discrimination, or expropriation appears to fit only arbitrarily or accidentally with value’s form of objectivity.[52] Race is therefore not a simple analogy of the fetishism of commodities; rather it is the way that generalised commodity exchange reifies social relations that makes it possible for ‘race’ to emerge conceptually and practically in modern society.
The reification view of race really gains traction because it not only historically situates the beliefs of the avowed racist, but also the facticity-of-race view of the non-racist. That is, one might be tempted by a functionalised approach to account for racial ideology out of self-interested and strategic ideological manipulation by a dominant race or class. But even those with a sincere desire to eradicate racism, or at least mitigate its effects, frequently adopt a taken-for-granted view of race as natural or given fact.[53] An ‘objective’ view of race—one that attempts to grasp race from a perspective outside the subjectively held beliefs of the racist—is characterised by the same form as, even if its content is the opposite of, racist ideology.
In this view, racism is the product of an unmediated, given set of attitudes, ‘tastes,’ or ‘preferences’ of the individuals who hold those views about, likewise, objectively given races.[54] Racism is a manifestation of animus or hatred or, less explicitly, intentional or disparate treatment, whether conscious or unconscious, of one race against another. Inequalities of race, expressed socially in differences in status, income, political influence, education, and so forth, are understood as the effect of such attitudes, norms, or institutions. Even from the standpoint of institutional or structural racism, race often retains its thingly facticity. In this perspective, racism is institutionalised in the facially-neutral rules, laws, or practices of organizations, firms, or states that nevertheless have racially-disparate impacts. But as long as those impacts are assessed like a treatment effect in a counterfactual causal model, the concept of race will preserve its unmediated, factual fixity. In fact, as Kohler-Hausmann persuasively demonstrates, the distinction between disparate treatment (intentional) and disparate impact (unintentional) racial discrimination only makes sense if race is simply defined as skin color, phenotype, or some other physical or social signifier.[55] Unless one acknowledges that these practices are part of the constitution of race itself, the notion that race can simply be toggled off or on, as if it was just phenotype, will persist.[56] Thus, in all of these anti-racist views, race remains a given, a taken-for-granted category.
Before moving on to the next section, I offer four clarifying points about the preceding account of race and reification. First, I wish to emphasise that fetishism is not equivalent to consciousness or ideology. It is not a theory of consciousness, but neither does it have nothing to do consciousness.[57] It is better described as the way the social world of commodities presents itself immediately to consciousness as observed in a pre-conscious or unreflective conscious way. How this unreflective consciousness is brought into reflective consciousness is an interpretive act—certainly an inevitable act, but no less interpretative for that.[58] Moreover, given that interpretative stage, the ‘sense data’ available to consciousness does not cause racist ideology or beliefs, at least not in any sort of deductive, unique, or immediate way.[59] Nevertheless, the value form’s objectivity has definite predispositions for acts of interpretation, especially as they interact with other prevailing assumptions about the nature of the world, social and natural, and which are not free of extant economic or political biases and ‘interests.’ For these reasons ofinterpretation, we can say that racist ideology, in its manifold forms, including its construction as a natural category, is anexpression of capitalist commodity relations.[60]
Second, for these reasons, the theory of reification and commodity fetishism is not a ‘pierce the veil’ theory of race and the relationship between reality and representation. That is, reification is not reducible to an ideological representation, a sort of veil that covers a deeper, more fundamental reality, and which requires only an intellectual debunking for this false belief to be eliminated.[61] To the contrary, destroying the false semblance of race—including in its more explicit, reflective, and ideological forms—does not abolish its material form, to paraphrase Marx on value.[62] The form of objectivity, the fetish character described earlier, established in commodity exchange is a process that operates ‘behind the backs’ of the producers themselves—i.e., without their direct conscious awareness—and will itself nurture the ‘false semblance’ of race even after it is demonstrated to be a social construction.[63] Value and race have a practical validity; their ‘falsity’ resides not in their existence sans phrase, but in their seemingly immediate, pre-social existence. The reification theory of race is therefore not just consistent with, but explanatory of, the persistence and resurgence of race in our contemporary times, where race stubbornly survives even in the wake of the civil rights and anticolonial movements.
Third, because everyone in capitalist society inhabits this world of commodities, no one has the privilege of being exempt from its self-presentation. The reification theory of race is not a standpoint epistemology, and does not promise, as some necessary process of social change, that a privileged subject will, in a moment of subject-object identity, see purely through the world of commodities. (In any case, as I have just insisted, the problem of representation—as if race were some pure error—is secondary to the real epistemological issue: race’s seeming facticity.) At the same time, this hardly means that the effects of reification are uniform—once again, as if interpretation were a mechanical and deductive causal process. The conditions of the colonised in a relatively pre-commodified society may, for example, be experienced in sharply different ways than the colonisers, who bring to their colonies the experience and epistemology of their commodified societies. Du Bois, as well as Fanon, recognised that the racially dominated may experience, through a ‘double consciousness,’ a profound diremption within their subjectivity that calls into question the objectified category of ‘race.’[64] Nevertheless, the crucial point is that because no one is exempt from the social world in which they live, nor the historicised epistemologies that come with them, there is no necessary guarantee that anyone will transcend this division between subject and object, between one’s own experience of race and its seeming facticity.[65]
Fourth, just as it is common to refer to race as a social construction it also common to treat race normatively as a form of inequality or difference.[66] However, the race-as-reification view presented in this article necessarily suggests instead a critique of race as a form of domination. A complete account of this problem would require exploring the meaning of domination and why race and racialization count as forms of domination. Also crucial to this account would be how reification partly constitutes racial domination through an act of subject-object inversion, by substituting ‘race’ for racism.[67] The question, again, is how this inversion takes place. I would contend that the form of objectivity constituted by the creation of value also accounts for the inversion of race and racism, and that reification is therefore essential for understanding how, within capitalism, racial domination instead comes to be seen as a problem of difference or inequality. That argument, however, must await another time, and for that reason, this article does not claim to offer, by any means, a complete treatment of race, racialization, and racial domination.[68]
Race and Its Reproduction
This section uses the concept of reification to untangle race’s tenacious attachment to capitalism. Nancy Fraser pointedly asks what accounts for capitalism’s ‘persistent entanglement with racial oppression’?[69] Similarly, Chris Chen acknowledges the deep and obstinate relation between race and capital: ‘“Race” is not extrinsic to capitalism or simply the product of specific historical formations such as South African Apartheid or Jim Crow America.’[70] This section argues that this association cannot be understood in terms of a functional relationship, which is where Marxist approaches to race have traditionally turned. Rather, it is only at an epistemological and ontological level—the level on which the fetishism of commodities and, more generally, reification operate—that this association can grasped.
What accounts for capital’s persistent entanglement with racial domination? Traditionally, Marxist approaches to race have been pitched at a functional level. Race exists because it is functional for capital. Racism either facilitates the accumulation of capital or serves the interests of capitalists, by dividing the working class and impeding the emergence of a revolutionary class consciousness. The limitations of a functional analysis are well known, and examples of the failure of functional analysis are easy to multiply. For instance, the Nazi regime’s antisemitism may have served the interests of German industrial capital, but this view makes it difficult, if not impossible, to grasp other crucial dimensions of Nazi antisemitism. The operation of the extermination camps wasnot a benefit to capitalists, which drew away resources from industrial production, and even impeded the Nazi war effort.[71] Moishe Postone emphasises this, pointing out that the extermination of the Jews was scarcely a means to an end ‘but was its own goal—extermination in order to exterminate—a goal which acquired absolute priority.’[72] Racial domination cannot be reduced to its functional effects.
As other recent contributions have recognised, a traditional Marxian focus on waged labour also frustrates the attempt to understand the ubiquity of ‘gratuitous violence’ in antiblack racism, both historically and contemporarily.[73] Assuming that the ‘privileged subject’ ‘is a subaltern who is approached by variable capital—a wage,’ distorts the nature of the domination of the unwaged, those who stand outside the wage relation.[74] Unable to directly apprehend the unwaged relation, this assumption makes that relation derivative to the waged relation. The assumption also obscures the way that those standing in an unfree or unwaged relation to capital have historically conferred, as their social others, a privileged political status on waged labour and helped to bring workers within the ambit of ‘free citizens.’ Finally, the assumption underscores a progressive view of capitalism, which would, sooner or later, eliminate racism as the expanding circuits of capital would bring more and more previously excluded dependents into the wage relation. As our present-day ‘planet of slums’[75] makes conspicuous, this view of capitalism has not been born out. Ultimately, viewing race through the lens of wage labour amounts to what Postone has described as an affirmative critique of capitalism, one made from the standpoint of labour and the improvement of waged work within capitalism, rather than its abolition.[76]
Several recent contributions have, in my view, successfully responded to the wage-labour critique of Marxist approaches to race. In short, capital’s drive to accumulate entails the constant expulsion and expropriation of labour, creating massive surplus populations in excess of any functional requirement of capitalism.[77] However, even those who avoid an affirmative critique of class and capital still tend to explain racial domination in terms of its function for capital. Nancy Fraser, for example, contrasts wage-based exploitation with expropriation, and rightly conceives of the latter as a mode of accumulation that doesnot depend on the wage relation.[78] Yet tying race and capital together through expropriation (rather than exploitation) still cognises race as functional for capital: ‘Expropriation lowers capitalists’ costs of production, supplying inputs for whose reproduction they do not fully pay.’[79] In other words, according to Fraser, racial domination exists because race-as-expropriation facilitates capital accumulation.
Likewise, in an illuminating contribution, Chris Chen effectively criticises and avoids the problems with a Marxist view of race made from the standpoint of waged labour. ‘In these [traditional Marxist] accounts,’ Chen acknowledges, ‘“race” becomes a functional or derivative component of class rule.’[80] More carefully than Fraser, Chen avoids the language of ‘expropriation as accumulation,’ and brings vivid attention to the ‘superfluity’ that capital renders to staggering numbers of humanity.[81] Nevertheless, even Chen seems to slip into functional language, asserting that ‘[c]apitalism … has required the systematic racialisation of … labour,’ as much through the wage relation as through its absence.[82] While avoiding the ‘privileged subject’ of the waged labourer, the problem with this formulation is that if capital requires racialization, how is racialization also not functional for capital? At the very least, Chen leaves open the question: if the relation between capital and race is not a functional one, what is it?
There is an even more fundamental problem with a functionalist analysis of race and class. This problem is that the functional relation between race and class can only be contingent. An interesting historical feature of capital is its social autonomy, both independent from direct formal relationships (i.e., status) and as social form.[83] As a real abstraction, capital exhibits an absolute indifference to other social forms. Marx’s method, to the extent it relies on abstraction, is not a clever way to marginalise the existence of racial domination, but rather a method adequate to the phenomenon under examination.[84] Chen recognises this, but in doing so inadvertently admits a serious incongruity. Chen writes, ‘If capital is first and foremost an indirect or impersonal form of domination (unlike black chattel slavery or feudalism, for example), in which production relations are not subordinated to direct social relations, there is no necessary incompatibility between this and the persistence or growth of direct, overt forms of racial and gender domination.’[85] Yet, the incongruity is that, by precisely the same token, there is neither any necessary functional connection between capital accumulation and race (or gender) domination. If capital as an impersonal and abstract form of social domination is indifferent to the existence of labour in free or unfree forms, then it is necessarily indifferent to the non-existence of unfree and racialised labour. To stress this point, as a functional matter, capital is indifferent to the continued existence or non-existence of racial domination. Once again, we need to look for the ‘persistent entwinement’ of race and capital somewhere other than in capital’s functional requirements.
This is hardly to deny that racial domination has exactly these functional effects for capital. Racialised wage differentials and occupational segmentation fragment the working class, frustrating its formation into a class for itself. Formal and informal status differentiation generates privileged free and ‘unfree’ (or ‘undeserving’) political categories of citizenship, further undermining social and political opposition to capital. Racialised expropriation and colonization ‘cheapens’ the costs of capital accumulation. All of these effects and more are too agonizingly true to be questioned. These functional effects undoubtedly figure heavily into any account of the reproduction of racial domination. I only deny that such functional effects are sufficient to account for theexistence of race, in light of that functional account’s evident shortcomings. One need only recall the example of the Nazi extermination camps mentioned previously.
Rather than locate the ‘persistent entanglement’ of race and capital in their functional imbrication, this article proposes that we find it in the ontological and epistemological horizon of the exchange society. By situating this as an epistemo-ontological problem we raise a different question about race: not how race functions for the origin reproduction of capitalism, whether as expropriation or exploitation, but what is race and how do we know it?[86] Throwaway concepts, such as operationalizing definitions, are inadequate to this task. Rather than begin with a definition, the understanding of a concept and its object requires as much thought and analysis as the functional analysis of race and capital.[87]
Following on race’s problematic standing in the functioning of capital, it is not surprising that critiques of affirmationist approaches to race and capitalism are pitched at an ontological level. For example, the writing of Frank Wilderson is replete with the language of ‘being’ and ‘ontology.’ Wilderson writes, ‘[V]iolence against black people is ontological and gratuitous as opposed to merely ideological and contingent.’[88] Wilderson argues that violence against black people—antiblackness—is what constitutes blackness in modern society. Wilderson wants us to understand what the nature of black being is, not how it functions for some other end. In a traditional Marxist or waged-labour view, ‘racism is read off the base, as it were, as being derivative of political economy.’[89] In contrast to its functional instrumentalization, the gratuity and pointlessness of antiblack violence underscores the ontological status of the black subject.
But we have to be clear about what sort of ontology we are after in this approach to race. By raising questions about the existence and nature of race, ontology responds to a genuine ‘need,’ a ‘lack,’ as Adorno calls it, that is left by functional analysis and a factualizing positivism.[90] However, ontology is a slippery subject. Pointing to ‘being’ promises something fundamental, absolute—even immediate—by exploiting an ambiguity in the term itself. ‘Being’ suggests something prior to or outside mind, something independently existing, and yet, because ‘being’ is distinct from concrete, individual beings, this usage actually obscures its more properly conceptual status.[91] In Wilderson, the search for a fundamental grounding is evident where, after objecting to the Gramscian attempt to ‘read’ racism ‘off the base,’[92] he proposes substituting ‘white supremacy as a matrix constituent to the base, if not the base itself.’[93] The immediacy of this form of black being is also evident in the putatively non-discursive images of violence and the body. Wilderson writes, for example, ‘State violence against the black body … is not contingent, it is structural and, above all, gratuitous.’[94] Thus, appeals to being and ontology are often ontologizing, and run the risk of attempting to ground claims outside of subjectivity and history.
In addition to avoiding the pitfalls of functional accounts of race, the race-as-reification view advanced in this article also avoids the problems ahistorical ontology. The kind of ontology proposed here is a critical one, a negative ontology. Appeals to being or existence cannot be made outside the historical conditions and subjective categories that establish them. Ontology, according to Adorno, encourages us not to be ‘hindered from pursuing that which ultimately matters.’[95] But ‘if this claim still survives, then it can genuinely do so only in the form of critique, which has taught us that the attempt to grasp ‘being’ immediately is impossible.’[96] Being, in whatever shape or form, is always conceptually and subjectively mediated, however violently, objectively, and structurally it is constituted. Because any possible being is subjectively mediated, there exists the possibility that the objective constitution of that being will appear ‘wrongly’ to consciousness, even if practically valid. This is the case with value—as well as race. Like value, race exists and does not exist. Race has a practical validity, not a natural one. Race has no existence outside historically specific, and conceptually mediated, circumstances. The goal of a critical ontology is to demonstrate this contradiction, to show why ‘race’ is a false ‘being,’ why race does not exist, but also why it persists and subsists as an apparent fact or natural object.
We reach a contradiction. On the one hand, race and capital are autonomous. They are distinct social forms. One cannot adequately account for race by instrumentalizing it in terms of functions or interests. Even speaking in terms of the ‘material interests’ of the racially dominant group cannot account for cases where the annihilation of a ‘race’ acquires such an absolute priority that it requires sacrificing those exact material interests. On the other hand, racism and capitalism are inextricably linked. Not only are race and capital intimately connected in their mutual, historical constitution, but capitalism contributes to the reproduction of race with all of its cold, ‘colorblind,’ indifference. If there is a determinate negation of this contradiction it lies in the commodity structure of capitalism itself. The varying degree of overlap between race and class that we observe historically and comparatively demonstrates, at a functional and causal level, the contingent nature between them. That functional-contingent relationship, however, is ontologically rooted in the reified structure of the exchange society. The value form that constitutes race and capital as autonomous forms of domination is what unites their existence. Furthermore, once historically and contingently joined, value’s reflection form makes that history disappear. Consequently, the notion that white supremacy could be eradicated under capitalism—the notion that there could be a race-neutral form of domination—strikes me, like Hegel’s moon falling to the earth, as the kind of abstract possibility whose actuality finds no adequate ground within present-day society. The struggle against racism and capitalism cannot be separated.
Race and Its Critique
Also finding limitations in class-based views of race, other writers have turned toward Marx’s theory of commodity fetishism to glean insights into the sources of modern racism. Moishe Postone pioneered this approach, applying it to the Jewish Holocaust and modern antisemitism.[97] More recently, Hylton White has built on Postone’s interpretation to develop a theory of antiblack racism.[98] This section will compare Postone’s and White’s accounts with this article’s analysis, in order to clarify the present argument and point to alternative paths forward.
According to Postone and White, antisemitism and antiblack racism are the fetishised forms of appearance of different, abstract dimensions of capitalism, money and labour, respectively. For Postone, in modern antisemitism, the Jews become a personification of ‘money,’ which he describes ‘as the manifestation of the purely abstract … form of the value dimension.’[99] For White, in antiblack racism, Blacks, and ‘above all the identification of blackness with the untamed biological,’ are ‘precisely the form that abstract labour assumes within its fetishised representation.’[100]
Both Postone’s and White’s analyses remain unsurpassed accounts of how capitalism’s commodity structure constitutes forms of racial domination. Ultimately, I largely agree with Postone and White that antisemitism and antiblack racism are fetish forms associated with the commodity structure of capitalism. Where I differ is in, first, precisely what those forms represent and, second, exactlyhow these processes of fetishization (or reification) work. Let me first give a brief overview. As to the first point, I disagree with Postone and White that the abstract dimensions of capital and labour, respectively, have their forms of appearance in, respectively, the Jewish and Black ‘races.’[101] Rather, I argue that what in fact are arbitrary, contingent, and historical social circumstances—the place of the Jews in medieval and early modern Europe or the role of colonization and slavery in global history—appear as properties of these ‘races,’ as attributes that have a misattributed natural or even biological basis. As to the second point, it is precisely because the abstract social and relational dimensions of capitalism do not directly appear, as real abstractions that take place behind the backs of society’s members, that makes these contingent social and historical factors appear as the attributes of ‘race.’ Thus, it is not capitalism’s abstract dimensions that appear in the form of racialised subjects; rather, those abstract forms explain how what does appear is taken as fact, natural or otherwise.
Understanding these objections requires that we reconstruct both of these prior accounts. Postone is particularly concerned to explain why antisemitism, in worldview and practice, targets the Jews as a personification, or representation, of capitalism’s social dislocations. Postone explicates this personification by identifying how the attributes of the Jews are similar to those of capital itself, especially money. Modern antisemitism, according to Postone, attributes a peculiar form of power to the Jews. Perhaps all forms of racism attribute power to the other, Postone explains, but in antisemitism this power is ‘mysteriously intangible, abstract and universal.’[102] It is not a concrete power (material or sexual) but a hidden, conspiratorial power—an abstract power. ‘The Jews represent an immensely powerful, intangible, international conspiracy.’[103] Postone then reminds us that these are precisely the same characteristics shared by capital: ‘When one examines the specific characteristics of the power attributed to the Jews by modern anti-Semitism—abstractness, intangibility, universality, mobility—it is striking that they are all characteristics of the value dimension of the social forms analyzed by Marx.’[104]
Postone clarifies that the Jews became the personification of the abstract domination of capital ‘not because the Jews were consciously identified with the value dimension.’[105] Rather, Postone insists that anti-capitalist discontent became directed toward the Jews because capitalism is itself antinomical. Capitalism appears in two different, opposed dimensions, abstract and concrete. He derives this from the commodity itself, which has the ‘double character’ of being both use-value and value:
The effect of this externalization [i.e., the ‘doubling’] is that the commodity, although it is a social form expressing both value and use-value, appears to contain only the latter, i.e., appears as purely material and ‘thingly’; money, on the other hand, then appears to be the sole repository of value, i.e., as the manifestation of the purely abstract, rather than as the externalized manifest form of the value dimension of the commodity itself.[106]
As capitalism develops, this antinomical structure of capitalist society becomes more and more entrenched, with ‘both sides of the antinomy’ becoming ‘objectified’ and each appearing as ‘quasi-natural.’[107] Society comes to be understood more and more in organicist terms.[108] The division of society into concrete and abstract dimensions allows a positive, material, and industrial capitalism to become separated from a negative, abstract, and financial capitalism. ‘The opposition of its abstract and the concrete dimensions allows capitalism to be perceived and understood in terms of its abstract dimension alone; its concrete dimension can thereby be apprehended as noncapitalist.’[109] This separation acquires an increasingly Manichaean character.[110] ‘The opposition of the concrete material and the abstract becomes the racial opposition of the Arians and the Jews.’[111] Postone argues that the Jews become the personification of financial capitalism, not because of some conscious manipulation to exploit their status as such. Rather, capitalism’s division into positively-valued concrete and negatively-valued abstract dimensions itself permits the association of Jews with financial capitalism, and from thence their persecution and the horrors of the Holocaust.
White’s analysis of antiblack racism follows a similar arc, and extends Postone’s analysis without however erasing the particularities of antisemitism and antiblack racism as distinct forms of racial domination. Following Fanon, White says that what is striking about antiblack racism is its concrete, bodily form, which sets it apart from antisemitism.
The Black of antiblack racism is hated not as a member of a people but as a concrete bodily being. Unlike the Jew, the Black does not control others through the exercise of will. To be black is to be the opposite of control: an uncontrolled bodily energy. And the violence that this calls forth is a destruction of life in its concrete, corporeal, visible existence, rather than as the agent of a race. For Fanon, this is the key generic difference between the industrialised mass murder of the Holocaust and the ritualised destruction of the individual black body by a lynching mob.
The ‘polarised’ way that antisemitism and antiblack racism express themselves leads White to identify the source of this opposition in the dialectical contradiction of Marx’s concept of value. For Postone the Jews represent money or finance capital, ‘the human body of money.’[112] But, explains White, ‘[T]he other side to capital is labour. Indeed, they are the same thing in different appearances: both of them are moments in the manifestation of value.’[113] As White continues to argue, where the Jews are a representation or personification of (finance) capital, Blacks are a representation of labour, capital’s dialectical opposite.
Moreover, when labour does appear, it does so as ‘biological energy,’ unlike capital, which is ‘monetary intelligence.’[114] When labour appears, it does so in ‘its most brutish, biological expression: animal vigour.’[115] The forms of power expressed in capital and labour are also different. The power of money is ‘cunning,’ while the power of labour is ‘brute.’[116] Labour ‘appears … as a visceral human capacity, intrinsically and constantly in need of external direction.’ Consequently, ‘Money is a power of control, but the biological body is a power that requires control.’[117] This contrast returns us to one of White’s most insightful points: that the commodity structure explains the modernity of ‘race’ across its different manifestations, but that antisemitism and antiblack racism are nevertheless distinct forms of racial domination.
Finally, why, in White’s account, does abstract labour take this form of appearance, in the ‘brute,’ ‘bodily,’ and ‘biological’ form of antiblack racism? For White, the history of slavery and colonialism is the crucial link that answers this question: ‘[T]he history of Atlantic slavery … and of European colonialism in Africa has bequeathed a lasting identification of Blacks with regimes of forced labour.’[118] The legacy of slavery and colonialism grounds the identifying association of antiblack racism as abstract labour’s form of appearance.
We are now in a position to discuss some of the limitations in these otherwise illuminating arguments. Both Postone and White argue that the racialised subjects of antisemitism and antiblack racism are said to represent different abstract dimensions of capitalism, capital and labour. Perhaps the most fundamental problem with this argument is that the abstract dimension of capital—value—already has its forms of appearance in capital’s variouseconomic categories: prices, money, rent, wages, profit, etc. The first three chapters ofCapital can be regarded as a painstaking effort to explain how value necessarily takes these forms. If value is already represented in these forms, why do they also take on different racial representations, as Postone and White argue? Of course, it is not impossible that value could have forms of appearance in addition to these categories. This duplication of appearances nevertheless raises doubts about whether the problem of race is understood as what capitalism’s abstract dimensions represent—or whether, as this article contends, it is better understood as what the abstraction of value does not represent, that is, what it forgets.
Let us take a closer look at Postone. Another of the difficulties in Postone’s argument is his insistence that capitalism appears in both concrete and abstract dimensions. Postone is correct, in my view, to link this with a particular, historically-situated epistemology. But what is characteristic about epistemology in capitalist society is that the abstract not only does not appear but does not ‘exist.’ In capitalism’s historical epistemology, ‘appearance’ is an empirical category and only ‘real,’ concrete objects appear. This epistemology is characterised by a ‘purist split,’ a hard-and-fast division between subject and object, mind and world, logic and experience.[119] ‘All rational cognition,’ says Kant, ‘is either material and concerned with some object, orformal and occupied only with the form of the understanding and of reason itself …’[120] Thus there is a real, independent world of concrete, material objects and a logical and abstract world of the mind. In this dualist epistemology the abstract does not appear.[121] Rather, everything concrete is part of the empirically given ‘real’ world and assigned a ‘thingly’ status while, in contrast, everything abstract is associated with pure mind. Postone’s argument depends crucially on establishing the link between finance capital and antisemitism by identifying the Jews with this abstract dimension of capitalism’s appearances. But if capitalism’s abstract dimensions do not directly appear—in other words, do not appear as abstract—then Postone cannot explain how the Jews become associated with finance capital.[122]
We can push this line of critique even further, contrasting Postone’s claim with how Marx talks about money’s thingly, non-abstract appearance. Postone references Marx’s concept of the double character of value and use-value, saying that money is the ‘sole repository of value’ or the ‘manifestation of the purely abstract.’[123] Marx does in fact emphasise the universality of money as a general commodity. Marx even remarks, ‘Exchange … produces a differentiation of the commodity into two elements, commodity and money, an external opposition which expresses the opposition between use-value and value which is inherent in it.’[124] To that extent, Postone’s association of money with the abstract dimension of the commodity (its value as distinct from its use-value) is correct. But it is not quite so simple, as Marx makes clear in the passage immediately following: ‘On the other hand, both sides of this opposition are commodities, hence themselves unities of use-value and value.’[125] Money is therefore just as much use-value as it is representation of value, and, as such, is prone to all of the fetishism of the commodity—in fact, even more prone. As we have already seen, Marx writes pervasively about our unreflective perception of money as a ‘thing,’ as distinct from its being an expression of value, as stressed by Postone. Marx says, ‘All the illusions of the Monetary System arise from the failure to perceive that money, though a physical object with distinct properties, represents a social relation of production.’[126] Thus, the conception of capitalist society is not that money appears as value’s abstract dimension, but that the abstract value form, although expressed in various forms of appearance including money, appears concretely rather than abstractly. In capital’s historically-given epistemology, capitalism appears concrete through and through. This is problematic for Postone, who argues that it is because capitalism appears in both abstract and concrete dimensions that Jews become the representation of abstract money or capital.[127]
There are similar challenges with White’s analysis of antiblack racism. According to White, the Black body in need of discipline and control is a representation of abstract labour, that is, of labour under capitalism. However, abstract labour is not capital’s dialectical opposite; rather, abstract labour is capital. White writes, ‘Most importantly, the other side to capital is labour. Indeed, they are the same thing in different appearances: both of them are moments in the manifestation of value.’[128] But this expression actually reverses the order of the presentation of the categories. Abstract labour is not a manifestation of value, but the source of value. Marx describes abstract labour as the substance of value.[129] More precisely, capital is one of abstract labour’s forms of appearance: abstract labour is value, value’s finished form is money, and money, in its most adequate expression (as value in-process) is capital.[130] It is true that labour and capital appear as opposites under capitalism, each generating distinct forms of ‘return,’ wages and profit (or interest). But then we no longer have a problem of representation: the Black body cannot be the representation of abstract labour because abstract labour—value—is already represented by (or, appears as) wages and profit. Similar to the problem in Postone’s account, if value already has its forms of appearances, in wages and profits, why does value—or abstract labour, in White’s approach—also appear in the form of the racialised subjects of antiblack racism?
It might be better not to see antiblack racism as a ‘representation’ of abstract labour, or indeed, of anything else. Rather, to paraphrase Marx, racialised subjects ‘appear as what they are,’ that is, as reified stereotypes of historically-contingent social relations. The explanation for antiblack racism is not that the black body represents abstract labour in need of discipline and control, as White would propose. Race in its antiblack form emerges, rather, as the reified ‘cause’ of what are in reality the consequences of the social and historical production of this racialised category. The black body is in need of discipline and control because the actual social and historical process of colonial enslavement, domination, and control vanish within these reified social relations. These processes ‘appear’ in a set of biologically or culturally innate characteristics imputed to a racialised category that necessitate discipline and control. This inversion is made possible by the fetish character of the value form, which makes society a material, rather than a social, relation between persons. Within this reified social world, antiblack racism misattributes outcomes of capitalism and colonialism to the characteristics of a particular ‘race.’
We can also explain modern antisemitism in terms more consistent with Postone himself, who writes, ‘The structure of alienated social relations which characterise capitalism has the form of a quasi-natural antinomy in which the social and historical do not appear.’[131] In my alternative construal, the Jews do not represent capitalism’s most ‘abstract’ elements, but are made to bear the burden of capitalism’s not conforming with the abstract and formal laws prescribed to it by bourgeois political economy.[132] One consequence of the reified world of commodities is the attempt to describe (concrete) objects according to (abstract) laws. For Lukács, for example, because this objectivity is separated from any broader social processes, these laws take on an increasingly formal character. Synthesizing the world of objects and appearances, capitalism is assumed, like the natural world, to operate under self-regulating and self-equilibrating objective laws. There is therefore something inexplicable when economic crises occur, or whenever social upheavals and dislocations of capitalism do not obey these formal laws of ‘second nature.’[133] A product of capital’s own contradictory movements, these economic catastrophes operate outside the conscious control of any individual member of society. Certain individuals or institutions—banks, financiers—stand in proximate relation to these crises and perhaps even to stand to benefit and, at the very least, are shielded from them. Because the abstract relation of value is not immediately apparent to consciousness, we observe only their concrete appearances: prices, use-values, money, profits. Just as the fetishism of commodities imputes value as a natural property of the commodity itself, capitalism’s woes, which are in fact immanent to capital, are assigned to seemingly concrete individuals and institutions: ‘the Jews.’ On the one hand, according to the impersonal domination of the law of value, no single individual or group can be assigned blamed for capitalism’s catastrophes. On the other hand, political economy’s ‘proper’ and formal laws of the economy (e.g., a self-equilibrating and harmonic system of exchange with a rational allocation of resources),requires that someone must be blamed. Under the abstract laws of reified consciousness, capitalism’s crises cannot not be the product of capitalism itself, since this would defy its formal laws, based on an understanding of capitalism as a world of objects, a social relation between things. Rather it is the greed, cunning, or deviousness of a particular ‘race,’ historically associated with finance, that must bear responsibility for capitalism’s shortcomings.
In this argument antisemitism is not the identification of capitalism’s abstract forms with the Jews, because the abstract never appears as such. Value already appears concretely in the form of money. As to what the racialised ‘Jews’ represent or personify, it is not the abstract dimension of capitalism, but all of capitalism’s crises and dislocations, which are inconsistent with its fetishised apprehension as a rational and formalised process of allocating resources. As to how this personification arises, we agree with Postone that it is not merely the product of scapegoating or an irrational, atavistic prejudice. However, in contrast to Postone, the Jews are not personified as capitalism’s abstract dimension through capitalism’s antinomical appearance, as concrete versus abstract, because, as I have argued, capitalism appears concrete through and through. Rather, it is precisely because the abstract, historical, and social do not (directly) appear within capitalist exchange relations that what is actually historically contingent (i.e., the relationship between Jews and finance) is hypostatised as the biological properties of a racialised group. In this reified view, capitalism’s social dislocations are not the result of capital’s abstract and contradictory drive to accumulate profit but are caused by a powerful conspiracy of concrete individuals and institutions. The same processes can be said to operate in antiblack racism, as described in our discussion of White. Given the very different histories and social relations, those processes yield two very different forms of ‘race.’
Conclusion
This article has tried to answer a few questions: how is it possible for race to be a social but misattributed natural category? How are race and capital both autonomous and imbricated? Rather than recapitulate the answers to those questions, the conclusion will discuss what ‘race’ can teach us about the nature of our exchange society. In their brilliant book Racecraft, Barbara Fields and Karen Fields pose the following question: Is race true or false, rational or irrational? Comparing race to the practice of ‘witchcraft’ in historical or non-capitalist societies, they are puzzled by our modern sensibility to accept race as ‘real’ or rational but witchcraft as false or irrational.[134] Both however, are founded on false assumptions and yet have a legitimate social validity for those who practice them. It is therefore a ‘mistake’ to treat one as rational the other as irrational, when they should both be judged the same, either both false or both true.
The Fields’ question is the same that which confronts scholars in the Marxist tradition when grappling with the nature of the fetishism surrounding the commodity. The current trend demotes talk about the ‘false semblance’ of value. For example, according to William Clare Roberts, ‘Fetishism is … first and foremost’ a political problem concerning domination and freedom ‘and an epistemic problem only derivatively.’[135]
Yet, ultimately, to ask whether value is true or false does not do justice to the complexity of the problem. Our deep ambivalence about ignoring the falsity of race explains why. For Marx, value is a true contradiction. While ‘[n]ot an atom of matter enters into the objectivity of commodities as values,’[136] and so the naturalization of value is false, value nevertheless has a ‘social validity.’ Value is therefore both true and false. Likewise with race.[137] Race is true because it has a practical validity. Race is false because these practices are premised on the epistemic error that race has an objectivity that exists outside of these practices of race domination. If we are less inclined to accept the falsity of race as truth, neither should would shirk from acknowledging the falsity of value. To insist on the falsity of value is neither to succumb to delusion nor to believe that freedom is found merely by piercing the veil of illusion. Rather, what is delusion is to believe that one can practically transform the real objectivity of race or value without a conscious contestation of their false reflections. Marx never flinched from attacking the ‘false semblance [falschen Scheins]’[138] of value because of the way the ‘bourgeois political economy’ bolstered—and continues to bolster—the taken-for-granted, thingly nature of value into capitalist apologetics.[139] Destroying the false semblance of race or value will not abolish their material form, but neither is the abolition of value’s or race’s form of objectivity possible without the critique of their forms of appearance.
Bibliography
Adorno, Theodor W. 1973, Negative Dialectics, New York: Continuum.
Adorno, Theodor W. 1976, ‘Sociology and Empirical Research’, in The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology, 68–86, edited by Theodor W. Adorno et al., translated by Glyn Adey and David Frisby, London: Heinemann.
Adorno, Theodor W. 2000, Metaphysics: Concepts and Problems, edited by Rolf Tiedemann, translated by Edmund Jephcott, Cambridge, UK: Polity Press
Adorno, Theodor W. 2019, Ontology and Dialectics, edited by Rolf Tiedemann, translated by Nicholas Walker, Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Adorno, Theodor W. and Walter Benjamin 1999, The Complete Correspondence, 1928–1940, Boston: Harvard University Press.
Balibar, Etienne and Immanuel Wallerstein 1991, Race, Nation, Class: Ambiguous Identities, London: Verso.
Becker, Gary S. 1957, The Economics of Discrimination, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Best, Beverley 2015, ‘Distilling a Value Theory of Ideology from Volume Three of Capital’,Historical Materialism, 23(3): 101–41.
Bhandar, Brenna and Alberto Toscano 2015, `Race, Real Estate and Real Abstraction’, Radical Philosophy, 194: 8–17.
Chen, Chris 2013, ‘The Limit Point of Capitalist Equality: Notes Toward an Abolitionist Antiracism’, Endnotes 3: 202–23.
Davis, Mike 2006, Planet of Slums, London: Verso.
Desmond, Matthew and Mustafa Emirbayer 2009, ‘What is Racial Domination?’, Du Bois Review, 6(2): 335–55.
Du Bois, W.E.B., 2008 [1903], The Souls of Black Folk, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Elbe, Ingo 2020, ‘Reification and Real Abstraction in Marx’s Critique of Political Economy’ in Marx and Contemporary Critical Theory: The Philosophy of Real Abstraction, 249–264, edited by Antonio Oliva et al., London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Fanon, Frantz 2008 [1952], Black Skin, White Masks, New York: Grove Press.
Feenberg, Andrew 2013, ‘Reification and Its Critics’ in Georg Lukács Reconsidered: Critical Essays in Politics, Philosophy and Aesthetics, edited by Thompson, M.J., London: Continuum.
Feenberg, Andrew 2014, The Philosophy of Praxis: Marx, Lukács, and the Frankfurt School, London: Verso.
Fields, Karen E. and Barbara J. Fields 2014, Racecraft: The Soul of Inequality in American Life, London: Verso.
Fraser, Nancy 2016, ‘Expropriation and Exploitation in Racialized Capitalism: A Reply to Michael Dawson’, Critical Historical Studies, 3(1):163–178.
Gabel, Joseph 1978, False Consciousness: An Essay on Reification, translated by Margaret A. Thompson with assistance by Kenneth A. Thompson, New York: Harper & Row.
Golash-Boza, Tanya 2016, ‘A Critical and Comprehensive Sociological Theory of Race and Racism’, Sociology of Race and Ethnicity, 2(2): 129–41.
Hall, Timothy 2011, ‘Reification, Materialism, and Praxis: Adorno’s Critique of Lukács’, Telos 155:61–82.
Habermas, Jürgen 1996, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, translated by William Rehg, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Haider, Asad 2018, Mistaken Identity: Race and Class in the Age of Trump, London: Verso.
Heinrich, Michael 2012, An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx's Capital, translated by Alexander Locascio, New York: Monthly Review Press.
Henry, Paget 2005, ‘Africana Phenomenology: Its Philosophical Implications’, The CLR James Journal, 11(1): 79–112.
Horkheimer, Max and Theodor W. Adorno 2002, Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments, edited by Gunzelin Schmid Noerr, translated by Edmund Jephcott, Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Kant, Immanuel 1999, Practical Philosophy, translated and edited by Mary J. Gregor, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Kohler-Hausmann, Issa 2018, ‘Eddie Murphy and the Dangers of Counterfactual Causal Thinking about Detecting Racial Discrimination’ Northwestern University Law Review, 113(5): 1163–1228.
Lijster, Thijs 2017, ‘“All Reification Is a Forgetting”: Benjamin, Adorno, and the Dialectic of Reification,’ in The Spell of Capital: Reification and Spectacle, 55–66, edited bySamir Gandesha and Johan F. Hartle, Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.
Loveman, Mara 1999, ‘Is “Race” Essential?’, American Sociological Review, 64(6): 891–898.
Lukács, Georg 1971, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, translated by Rodney Livingston, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Martin, John Levi and King-To Yeung 2003, ‘The Use of the Conceptual Category of Race in American Sociology, 1937–99’, Sociological Forum 18(4): 521–543.
Martinot, Steve and Jared Sexton 2003, ‘The Avant-Garde of White Supremacy’, Social Identities, 9(2): 169–81.
Marx, Karl 1973, Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy, translated by Martin Nicolaus, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl 1976, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy Volume 1, translated by Ben Fowkes, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl 1976 [1847], The Poverty of Philosophy inMarx and Engels Collected Works Volume 6, New York: International Publishers.
Marx, Karl 1981, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy Volume 3, translated by David Fernbach, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Marx, Karl 1986 [1867], A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy inMarx and Engels Collected Works Volume 29, New York: International Publishers.
Marx, Karl 2016, Marx’s Economic Manuscript of 1864–1865, translated by Ben Fowkes, edited and with an introduction by Fred Moseley, Leiden: Brill.
Mattick, Paul 2019, Social Knowledge: An Essay on the Nature and Limits of Social Science, Leiden: Brill.
Mau, Søren 2018, ‘The Transition to Capital in Marx’s Critique of Political Economy’, Historical Materialism, 26(1): 68–102.
Murray, Patrick 2016, The Mismeasure of Wealth: Essays on Marx and Social Form, Leiden: Brill.
O'Connor, Brian 2004, Adorno’s Negative Dialectic: Philosophy and the Possibility of Critical Rationality, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
O’Kane, Chris 2020, ‘The Critique of Real Abstraction: From the Critical Theory of Society to the Critique of Political Economy and Back Again’, in Marx and Contemporary Critical Theory: The Philosophy of Real Abstraction, 265–287, edited by Antonio Oliva et al., London: Palgrave Macmillan
Pepperell, Nicole 2018, ‘Beyond Reification: Reclaiming Marx’s Concept of the Fetish Character of the Commodity’, Contradictions: A Journal for Critical Thought 2(2): 33–55.
Postone, Moishe 1980, ‘Anti-Semitism and National Socialism: Notes on the German Reaction to “Holocaust”’, New German Critique, 19: 97–115.
Postone, Moishe 1993, Time, Labor, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marx’s Critical Theory, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Postone, Moishe 2003, ‘Lukács and the Dialectical Critique of Capitalism’ in New Dialectics and Political Economy, 78–100, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Reichelt, Helmut 2007, ‘Marx’s Critique of Economic Categories: Reflections on the Problem of Validity in the Dialectical Method of Presentation in Capital’,Historical Materialism 15: 3–52.
Roberts, William Clare 2016, Marx’s Inferno: The Political Theory of Capital, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sellars, Wilfrid 1956, ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind’, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19): 253–329.
Smith, Tony 2014, ‘Hegel, Marx and the Comprehension of Capitalism’ in Marx's Capital and Hegel's Logic: A Reexamination, 15–40, edited by Fred Moseley and Tony Smith, Leiden: Brill.
Smulewicz-Zucker, Gregory R. 2020, ‘Linking Racism and Reification in the Thought of Georg Lukács’ in Confronting Reification: Revitalizing Georg Lukács’s Thought in Late Capitalism, 252–270, edited by Gregory R. Smulewicz-Zucker, Leiden: Brill.
Sohn-Rethel, Alfred 2020, Intellectual and Manual Labour: A Critique of Epistemology, translated by Martin Sohn-Rethel, Leiden: Brill.
Sorentino, Sara-Maria 2019, ‘The Abstract Slave: Anti-Blackness and Marx’s Method’, International Labor and Working-Class History, 96: 17–37.
Starosta, Guido 2017, ‘The Role and Place of “Commodity Fetishism” in Marx’s Systematic-dialectical Exposition in Capital’,Historical Materialism 25(3): 101–39.
Toscano, Alberto 2008, ‘The Open Secret of Real Abstraction’, Rethinking Marxism 20(2):273–87.
Wilderson, Frank, III 2003, ‘Gramsci’s Black Marxism: Whither the Slave in Civil Society?’, Social Identities, 9(2): 225–40.
White, Hylton 2013, ‘Materiality, Form, and Context: Marx contra Latour’, Victorian Studies, 55(4): 667–682.
White, Hylton 2020, ‘How is Capitalism Racial? Fanon, Critical Theory and the Fetish of Antiblackness’, Social Dynamics, 46(1): 22–35.
[1] For questions and comments, I wish to thank Guyora Binder, Luis Chiesa, Nate Holdren, Rob Hunter, Rob Knox, Ashok Kumar, Sarah Ludin, Athena Mutua, Sara Ludin, Tad Skotnicki, Tico Taussig-Rubbo, Dom Taylor, the editors of Historical Materialism, and two anonymous reviewers.
[2] Along with Chen 2013, p. 207, the term ‘race’ is used throughout this article not as an object to which independent causal properties are attributed, but rather as the consequence of ‘racial ascription’ or ‘racialization processes’ that ‘justify historically asymmetrical power relationships through reference to phenotypical characteristics and ancestry.’ See also Fields and Fields 2014, p. 16–19.
[3] Marx 1976, p. 149.
[4] Murray 2016, pp. 211, 213.
[5] Marx 1976, p. 168.
[6] Murray 2016. See also Feenberg 2013 and Elbe 2020 for more recent analyses of the relationship between fetishism and reification.
[7] Bewes 2002.
[8] Bewes does make several brief and scattered statements about race and racism which align with the argument of this article. See Bewes 2002, pp. 4, 75–76, 160, 174.
[9] Gabel 1975, pp. 119–136.
[10] Gabel 1975, pp. 86–87.
[11] Fraser 2016, pp. 163, 173.
[12] I am therefore in complete agreement with Postone 1980, p. 107: ‘The intention is not to negate socio-psychological or psychoanalytical explanations, but rather to elucidate a historical-epistemological frame of reference within which further psychological specifications can take place.’
[13] O’Kane 2020, p. 281.
[14] Bhandar and Toscano 2015.
[15] Toscano 2008.
[16] Toscano 2008, p. 277.
[17] Postone 1993, pp. 48–49.
[18] This passage is quoted in Lukács, who cites Marx precisely to undermine dialectically the hard Kantian distinction between subject and object, mind and world. It should be noted, however, that Marx uses the phrase in a different, more specific sense, namely, to challenge Kant’s critique of the ontological proof for the existence of God. Lukács 1971, p. 127.
[19] Murray 2016, pp. 120–188.
[20] Bhandar and Toscano 2015, p. 9; Toscano 2008, p. 281, both recognise this distinctive approach to real abstraction, whose explicit elaboration comes from Sohn-Rethel 1978.
[21] Adorno 1976, p. 80.
[22] For another noteworthy contribution, see Smulewicz-Zucker 2020.
[23] Postone 1980, p. 107.
[24] Etienne Balibar nicely distinguishes the newer, ‘cultural’ racism from the older, ‘biological’ racism: ‘[Current racism] is a racism whose dominant theme is not biological heredity but the insurmountability of cultural differences, a racism which, at first sight, does not postulate the superiority of certain groups or peoples in relation to others but ‘only’ the harmfulness of abolishing frontiers, the incompatibility of life-styles and traditions … .’ Balibar and Wallerstein 1991, p. 21. What unites these two forms of racism and makes the reification theory of race a suitable explanation for both, is that in either case the attributes or characteristics of the supposedly different races are the pre-social and invariant properties of the individual members, inherited either biologically or culturally.
[25] Desmond and Emirbayer 2009, p. 336; see also Golash-Boza, p. 2.
[26] Starosta 2017, p. 102 n. 1. Both White 2013 and Elbe 2020 also emphasize the objective, ‘real inversion’ of the commodity form.
[27] Marx 1976, p. 149.
[28] Starosta 2017, p. 102 n. 1.
[29] Marx 1976, p. 165.
[30]Marx 1976, p. 166.
[31] Patrick Murray draws a helpful distinction between ‘abstract labour as “physiological” labour’ and ‘“practically abstract” labour.’ Labour of any form, in any sort of society, can be considered abstract ‘[b]y making a distinction of reason,’ for example, by measuring chronologically the amount of undifferentiated physiological labour expended in production. But Murray argues, and I agree, that Marx thinks of abstract labour as labour that ‘society treats as abstract … in practice.’ ‘“Practically abstract” labour is socially validated in a way that shows society’s actual indifference toward labour’s specific character, that is, toward labour’s specific ways of transforming nature and toward the specific use-value characteristics of its end product.’ Murray 2016, pp. 136, see also 136–45. Heinrich 2012, pp. 50–51, makes a similar distinction.
[32] Marx 1976, p. 165.
[33] I wish to focus on the underlying continuities in the accounts of Marx, Lukács, and subsequent writers, including Adorno and Horkheimer. Like Lukács, Horkheimer and Adorno’s ‘Dialectic of Enlightenment could be read as an anthropological extension of the concept of fetishism.’ Hall 2011, p. 67. Adorno’s main objection is that Lukács’s reification is too subjective, and is fixated on the ‘reflection form’ rather than the objectivity—even if ‘false’—that lies beyond the subject. Adorno 1973; Hall 2011. In other words, Adorno says that Lukács reduces the fetish character of the commodity to fetishism. It should be clear in this article, that I am using reification in the more capacious sense that embraces both its objective and subjective dimensions.
[34] Lukács, 1971, p. 83
[35] Marx 1976, p. 166.
[36] Feenberg 2014, p. 86.
[37] Feenberg 2014, p. 86 (emphasis in original).
[38] Kohler-Hausmann 2018, p. 1169.
[39] Already, in the section on commodity fetishism, Marx alludes to the crucial role that money plays in making social relations disappear under capitalism: ‘It is however precisely this finished form of the world of commodities—the money form—which conceals the social character of private labour and the social relations between the individual workers, by making those relations appear as relations between material objects, instead of revealing them plainly.’ Marx 1976, p. 168–69.
[40] Marx 1976, p. 187.
[41] Marx 1976, p. 187. See also Adorno and Benjamin 1999, p. 321: ‘For all reification is a forgetting: objects become purely thing-like the moment they are retained for us without the continued presence of their other aspects: when something of them has been forgotten.’ Cited in Lijster 2017, p. 57.
[42] Marx 1976, p. 187.
[43] On the ‘asocializing’ effects of money, see also Murray 2016, pp. 290: ‘Because value, which is something purely social, appears, first, to be a natural property of a commodity (the fetishism of the commodity) and, still more perversely, to be a thing, money (the money fetish)—social relations seem to be absent.’ For further discussion, see pp. 290–93.
[44] Marx 1973, p. 157.
[45] Haider 2018, p. 46.
[46] Marx 1981, p. 961. See also the entire section on ‘The Trinity Formula’. Marx 1981, pp. 953–70.
[47] Typification versus individuation.
[48] Marx 1973, p. 84. Marx frequently reflects upon how the universalization of exchange relations underwrite bourgeois society’s conceptions of freedom and equality. Think, for example, of the famous passage on ‘Freedom, Equality, Property and Bentham,’ Marx 1976, p. 280. Elsewhere, he writes similarly: ‘[A]ll inherent contradictions of bourgeois society,’ says Marx, ‘appear extinguished in money relations as conceived in a simple form … .’ Marx 1973, p. 241. The exchange relationship is one of equality: ‘Each of the subjects is an exchanger; i.e. each has the same social relation towards the other that the other has towards him. As subjects of exchange, their relation is therefore that of equality.’ ibid.
[49] This is Patrick Murray’s phrase, not Marx’s, but it nicely captures what I believe is Marx’s meaning when he suggests that commodity relations reduce society to ‘material [dinglich] relations between people and social relations between things,’ Marx 1976, p. 166. See Murray 2016, pp. 211, 213.
[50] Murray 2016, p. 502: ‘It is not only that capitalist social relations naturally reproduce the ideologies of vulgar and classical political economy; they engender the many faces of bourgeois philosophy generally’ including ‘“state of nature” and social contract theories’; see also Habermas 1996, p. 44: ‘To be sure, the model of the social contract found support in the evidence that modern exchange society seemed to secure some thing like a natural autonomy and equality for private persons through their participation in market transactions.’
[51] Within the social sciences, these conceptions survive in the influential perspectives of ontological and methodological individualism. Although methodological individualism is said to eschew the more controversial claims of ontological individualism, it is hard to take these claims seriously. Otherwise, methodological individualism quickly collapses under its own weight.
[52] Left-wing liberalism has a curious way of recognizing the ‘historical,’ distinguishing between a possibly tainted origin of capitalism with the possibility of a perfectly just present-day capitalism. It recognises history only as a kind of artificial obstruction with a natural system of free and equal individual exchange. ‘Thus, there has been history, but there is no longer any.’ Marx 1976 [1847], p. 174.
[53] Loveman 1999.
[54] Becker 1957.
[55] Kohler-Hausmann 2018, p. 1175.
[56] Kohler-Hausmann 2018, p. 1171 n. 19. Kohler-Hausmann also cites Martin and Yeung 2003, pp. 521–25, who show ‘that although the constructivist position is explicitly embraced by social scientists, many fail to operationalize it in any meaningful way in their research methodology.’
[57] I take it that a basic starting point, beginning with Hegel, and continuing with Marx and the Frankfurt School, is the rejection of a hard dichotomy between subject and object. The tendency to describe fetishism as ideology or a purely subjective category is symptomatic of this dichotomised way of thinking.
[58] Beverly Best puts a similar point this way: ‘the perceptual economy of capital establishes the foundation, building blocks, or “raw material” for the development of collective imaginaries, common sense, and so on.’ Best 2015, p. 106; see also, pp. 107 n. 7, 120, 127.
[59] Nevertheless, it is certainly the case that ‘sense impressions’ are a cause of what it is that is being interpreted. See, e.g., Sellars 1956, p. 290; O’Connor 2004, p. 90.
[60] Another point that can be emphasised is that reification is not an ‘economism.’ While the reification theory avoids the reductionist problems of making race a problem of class, it would still be inaccurate to describe it as one where ‘the economy’ determines, in a causal sense, ‘race’ or ‘racial ideology.’ The main reason for this is that we are not describing a causal form of explanation. Race is the expression of a certain kind of society, rather than a functional effect of a hypostatised ‘part’ of society, e.g., ‘the economy.’ This kind of society happens to be a commodity-producing society.
[61] Pepperell 2018 criticises Lukács’ theory of reification as a ‘pierce the veil’ theory of knowledge and representation, a criticism I do not believe is entirely warranted.
[62] Marx 1976, p. 168.
[63] Marx 1976, p. 135. In this sense, the real abstraction of the world of commodities is critical for the abstract category of race to become objective (i.e., to have practical validity), whether or not one wants to think of race as a real abstraction in its own right.
[64] Du Bois, 2008; Fanon, 2008. See also Henry 2005.
[65] Perhaps the main problem with Lukács’s reification essay is the implication that the proletariat would achieve a ‘subject-object’ identity. Postone 2003.
[66] On problematic politics of ‘difference,’ see Chen 2013, p. 206.
[67] Karen Fields and Barbara Fields write that the production of race through racism ‘has permitted the consequence under investigation to masquerade among the causes’ and that the ‘substitution [of ‘race’ for ‘racism’] … transforms the act of a subject into an attribute of the object.’ Fields and Fields 2014, pp. 41, 96, 41. ‘Racecraft’ is the Fields’ terms for this subject-object reversal. ‘Like physical terrain, racecraft exists objectively; it has topographical features that American regularly navigate, and we cannot readily stop traversing it. Unlike physical terrain, racecraft originates not in nature but in human action and imagination.’ Fields and Fields 2014, p. 18.
[68] Also useful in this discussion of racial domination would be the roles of ‘double consciousness,’ in Du Bois 2008 and Fanon 2008, and the related concepts, ‘personification’ and ‘character masks,’ which are counterparts to reification, in Marx 1976, p. 179; Heinrich 2012, pp. 88, 232n21.
[69] Fraser 2016, pp. 163, 167, 171, 173.
[70] Chen 2013, p. 214
[71] A functional interpretation, according to Postone, also results in the view that the Nazi extermination camps were instances of indiscriminate mass murder, murder in general, either misapprehending precisely who were among its victims, European Jews most conspicuously, or leaving them unexplained. Postone 1980, p. 101.
[72] Postone 1980, p. 105.
[73] Wilderson 2003, p. 237.
[74] Wilderson 2003, p. 225.
[75] Davis 2006.
[76] Postone 1993, p. 17, 64–71. Applying the idea of an affirmative critique to race, see Chen 2013, p. 207–08, 212.
[77] Chen 2013.
[78] Fraser 2016, pp. 166–69.
[79] Fraser 2016, p. 167.
[80] Chen 2013, p. 220, very astutely observes, ‘“Race” typically persists in academic Marxist discourse as a social division internal to the working class and sown by economic elites in order to drive down wages, fragment worker insurgency, and create the permanent threat of a nonwhite reserve army of labour. In these accounts “race” becomes a functional or derivative component of class rule.’ However, Chen never fully makes clear how the colorblind process of stratification, superfluity, policing, and incarceration emphasised throughout the article are also not ‘functional’ components of, if not class rule, then the rule of capital.
[81] ‘From the point of view of capital, “race” is renewed not only through persistent racialised wage differentials, or the kind of occupational segregation posited by earlier “split labour market” theories of race, but through the racialisation of unwaged surplus or superfluous populations from Khartoum to the slums of Cairo.’ Chen 2013, p. 217.
[82] Chen 2013, pp. 214, 215 (emphasis in original).
[83] Reichelt 2007, pp. 5–6.
[84] For example, Sorentino 2019 lodges this critique, unsuccessfully in my view, against Marx’s method of abstraction.
[85] Chen 2013, p. 212.
[86] Adorno 2019, p. 36: ‘The linguistic form which is supposedly substantiated in the concept of being is the copula. The copula is simply nothing but the “is” in the predicative judgment A is B.’
[87] Adorno 2000, p. 5: ‘I believe that while philosophy may well terminate in definitions, it cannot start out from them.’
[88] Wilderson 2003, p. 229.
[89] Wilderson 2003, p. 225.
[90] Adorno 2019, pp. 104, 95–105. ‘[T]he influence exerted by the new ontology [i.e., of Heidegger and others] … is the perfect complement to positivism,’ p. 103.
[91] Adorno 2019, p. 90.
[92] Wilderson 2003, p. 225. The attempt at fundamental grounding is also evident in Sorentino 2019, which ‘moves to substitute the abstraction of labor with that of slavery,’ p. 17.
[93] Wilderson 2003, p. 231.
[94] Wilderson 2003, p. 229 (citing Martinot and Sexton 2003).
[95] Adorno 2019, p. 167.
[96] Adorno 2019, p. 167 (original emphasis).
[97] Postone 1980.
[98] White 2020.
[99] Postone 1980, p. 109.
[100] White 2020, p. 10.
[101] As I will also argue below, value, an abstract social relation, already has its forms of appearance in the economic categories analyzed by Marx: prices, wages, rents, profits and, above all, money. Furthermore, the relationship between money and antisemitism, central to Postone’s account, is more complicated than his presentation suggests.
[102] Postone 1980, p. 106.
[103] Postone 1980, p. 106.
[104] Postone 1980, p. 108.
[105] Postone 1980, p. 112 (emphasis added).
[106] Postone 1980, p. 109.
[107] Postone 1980, p. 109.
[108] Rather than in the eighteenth-century mechanical terms borrowed from Newton’s physics.
[109] Postone 1993, p. 174 n. 115.
[110] Postone 1993, p. 163; Postone 1980, p. 106.
[111] Postone 1980, p. 112; Postone 1993, p. 174 n. 115.
[112] White 2020, p. 9.
[113] White 2020, p. 10.
[114] White 2020, p. 10.
[115] White 2020, p. 10.
[116] White 2020, p. 10.
[117] White 2020, p. 10.
[118] White 2020, p. 11 (citations omitted). White’s answer to this seems to depart somewhat subtly from Postone. Although Postone acknowledges the association between modern antisemitism and its premodern, historical antecedents, he appears eager to distance himself from that connection, at least as the linchpin for his account. For White, by contrast, the historical is the link.
[119] Murray 2016, p. 69–70.
[120] Kant 1999, p. 43.
[121] Rather, as Lukács and others have made clear, bourgeois epistemology, to use a phrase borrowed from Murray 2016, p. 69–70, presents us with a ‘purist split.’
[122] We might also add that the Jews were not vilified by the Nazis because of their representation of the abstract dimension of capitalism, in contrast to its material and thingly ‘good’ dimension, but because finance capital, especially as credit and interest-bearing capital, appears as a concrete perversion of capital’s concrete dimension. Through the M–M´ circuit, interest ‘seems to derive from capital as its own independent source,’ inexplicably. Marx 1981, p. 968. It is not because money appears as abstract that makes this property of money suspect, but rather than the abstract social relations which are their actual basis does not appear in the circuit of exchange.
[123] Postone 1980, p. 109.
[124] Marx 1976, p. 199.
[125] Marx 1976, p. 199.
[126] Marx 1986 [1867], p. 276 (emphasis added). Marx also remarks, ‘But money is itself a commodity, an external object capable of becoming the private property of any individual. Thus the social power becomes the private power of private persons,’ Marx 1976, pp. 229–30. Further: ‘[T]he mystifying character’ of capitalist social relations ‘still more explicitly transform[s] the relation of production itself into a thing (money),’ Marx 1981, p. 965. For discussion, see Murray 2016, pp. 37–42, 290–92. See also Smith 2014, p. 31, for a brief recapitulation of the ‘thingness’ of money and its relation to value.
[127] Not only does the effort to establish the link between capitalism’s abstract dimension and antisemitism run into the problem that capitalism, in any dimension, does not appear directly as abstract, but there are also other complications in Postone’s account. If ‘[m]odern anti-Semitism involves a biologization of capitalism … as International Jewry,’ Postone 1980, p. 112, this should bring the Jews into the concrete, thingly, and positively-valued dimension of capitalism, according to Postone’s dichotomization of capitalism’s appearances.
[128] White 2020, p. 9.
[129] Marx 1976, pp. 125–31; for discussion of the use of the term ‘substance,’ see Heinrich 2012, p. 49.
[130] Mau 2018.
[131] Postone 1980, p. 109.
[132] Earlier in his essay, Postone 1980, p. 107, acknowledges, ‘It is not that the Jews merely were considered to be the owners of money, as in traditional anti-Semitism, but that they were held responsible for economic crises and identified with the range of social restructuring and dislocation resulting from rapid industrialization … .’ At this stage, what the racialised ‘Jews’ personify are the consequences of capitalism’s crises and development. Later, however, Postone shifts, and the Jews then come to represent ‘money,’ or capital in the abstract.
[133] Lukács 1971, p. 105: ‘[W]e see that it is the very success with which the economy is totally rationalised and transformed into an abstract and mathematically oriented system of formal ‘laws’ that creates the methodological barrier to understanding the phenomenon of crisis.’
[134] Fields and Fields compare what they call ‘racecraft’ with E. E. Evans-Pritchard’s famous study, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic Among the Azande. Fields and Fields 2014, p. 16. Evans-Pritchard’sWitchcraft is renowned for abstaining from any judgment about the ‘falsity’ regarding the beliefs about witchcraft among the Azande. Interestingly, Paul Mattick has also described Marx’s project inCapital in terms of Evans-Pritchard’s,Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic Among the Azande. Marx approaches not just the world of capital, but the way that we (including the ‘political economists’) interpret and experience this world, and how these particular forms of experience and interpretation can arise within the world they inhabit. Mattick 2020, p. xxi.
[135] Roberts 2017, p. 85.
[136] Marx 1976, p. 138.
[137] Horkheimer and Adorno 2002, pp. 137: Fascist antisemitism is ‘true and false at the same time. … [it] is true in the sense that fascism has made it true.’
[138] Marx 1976, p. 187.
[139] Marx 2016, p. 897.
Racism and Capitalism
A Contingent or Necessary Relationship
Anti-racist debate today remains polarized between “class reductionist” (any attempt to address racial disparities reinforces capitalist class relations) and “liberal identity” (disparities in racial representation can be resolved without questioning class inequality) politics. Both positions share a common perspective—racial oppression and class exploitation are the products of distinctive social dynamics whose relationship is historically contingent. This essay is an initial step toward astructurally necessary relationship between capitalism and racial oppression. The essay draws upon on Anwar Shaikh and Howard Botwinick’s elaboration of Marx’s political economy; and Ellen Wood’s analysis of the specificity of capitalism imperialism.
This piece is being made available as a preprint edition of the Race and Capital special issue of Historical Materialism. The final published version of this text will be made available on the Brill website in the coming months, we ask that citations refer to the Brill edition.
Issue 32(2&3): Race and Capital
The uprising sparked by the police murder of George Floyd in May 2020 has again placed the question of race at the center of politics.[1] While the right steadfastly denies the existence of racism and advocates greater repression against those protesting police violence, the left—both liberal and socialist—is scrambling to come to grips with the rebellion. For the liberals, the problem is simply a “lack of diversity”—the police, the middle classes, corporate America, and the political establishment do not “reflect” the population as a whole. The liberals hope to derail these struggles as they did those of the 1960s and 1970s, by promoting a new middle class of color without addressing the growing poverty and insecurity of working people of color. As Asad Haider[2] has argued, the neo-liberals have transformed “identity politics” from an attack on racism, sexism, and capitalism into a demand to diversify the political and economic elite without tampering with capitalist class relations.
The US socialist left is also attempting to catch up with events. The main organization of the U.S. left, the Democratic Socialist of America (DSA) was caught back-footed by these new struggles and has found it difficult to move from the routines of Democratic Party electoral politics to organizing an ongoing movement against racism and capitalism.[3] Some in DSA have failed to embrace the most radical demands of the uprising—to defund, disarm, and disband the police—and instead argue for continued campaigning around “universal” demands to raise wages and the funding of public services—including the police.[4]
Both the liberal “identitarian” and class reductionist positions, despite their divergent political trajectories, share a common conceptual starting point—they both view the relationship of racial oppression and capitalist exploitation as contingent rather thannecessary. This can be seen in radical and Marxian approaches to the relationship between racism and capitalism. While resting on very different theories of the origins and dynamics of capitalism, both Cedric Robinson’s[5] highly influential theorization of “racial capitalism,” and Ellen Meiksins Wood’s[6] assertion of the possibility of a “non-racial” capitalism view the relationship capitalist exploitation and racial oppression as historically contingent.
Robinson’s begins from the problematic ‘commercialization model,’ where capitalism emerges out of the revival of European trade and is consolidated in Europe’s imperial expansion and the creation of the early modern Atlantic economy.[7] Racism, according to Robinson, already existed in Europe as early as classical antiquity, making racial oppression’s relationship with capitalism contingent on capitalism’s alleged dependence on European expansion in the sixteenth through the eighteenth centuries. Robinson’s assertion of a “long duree” of European racism is based on a fundamental confusion between pre-capitalist and capitalist modes of differentiating human beings.[8]Black Marxism leaves open the possibility that if capitalism had emerged outside of “racialized” European feudalism, racism would not be a feature of capitalism.
Ellen Meiksins Wood, one of the most perceptive theorists of the origins and expansion of capitalism, also explicitly rejects any necessary relationship between capitalism and racial oppression:
At the very least, class equality means something different and requires different conditions from sexual or racial equality. In particular, the abolition of class inequality would by definition mean the end of capitalism. But is the same necessarily true about the abolition of sexual or racial inequality? Sexual and racial equality… are not in principle incompatible with capitalism…although class exploitation is constitutive of capitalism as sexual or racial inequalities are not, capitalism subjects all social relations to its requirements. It can co-opt and reinforce inequalities and oppressions that it did not create and adapt them to the interests of class exploitation.[9]
Wood confuses the theoretical and historical preconditions of capitalist social property relations with the results—the unintended consequences of the reproduction of these social property relations.[10] Wood argues, correctly, that racial oppression is not a necessary precondition for the establishment of capitalist social-property relations. The necessary preconditions of capitalist production are the emergence of producers and non-producers who are compelled to reproduce themselves through market competition—through the operation of the law of value. Historically, racism was the result, not the cause, of the global expansion of English capitalism in the 17th century. While not a precondition of capitalism, there are strong theoretical reasons to argue that racial oppression is anecessary consequence of the expansion and reproduction of capitalist social relations.
Similar methodological and theoretical problems haunt other attempts, influenced by notions of intersectionality, to analyze the relationship between capitalism and racial oppression. The roots of intersectionality can be found in the “dual systems” theories of gender oppression that emerged in the late 1970s. Many socialist-feminists had concluded that Marxism was a “gender blind” theory capable of grasping the dynamics of class exploitation, but possessing few insights into the dynamics of an independent “sex/gender” system of patriarchal oppression that coexisted with capitalism.[11] In the last twenty years, theories of intersectionality have expanded the notion of multiple systems to race, sexual preference, gender identity, and differential ability. While the earliest version of intersectionality saw distinct systems of class, gender, racial and other forms of oppression shaping social identities and practices, later versions have attempted a more integrative perspective. Patricia Hill Collins[12] collates oppressions in “matrices” and attempts to explore the interrelationships between different vectors of oppression. Ashley Bohrer’s[13] work is the most rigorous attempt to date to reconcile Marxism and intersectionality, arguing that capital’s social domination is based on both exploitation and oppression.
All of the variants of intersectionality suffer from a number of analytic problems. The earliest versions suffer from the same issues as dual-systems theory identified by Lise Vogel in the early 1970s—a failure to consistently specify the dynamics of patriarchy and its relationship to capitalism.[14] Holly Lewis, in her path-breaking analysis of gender and sexuality, argues that intersectionality “assumes that each system of oppression is a vector with a nebulous origin intersecting with the individual subject... Disconnected from material life, oppression seems it as if it “were born of ill will and bad ideas.”[15] Not only are the origins and trajectory of each separate “street” of oppression unspecified, but as Tithi Bhattacharya argues intersectionality fails to specify “the logic of their intersection.”[16] The later and more sophisticated versions of the theory avoid the “atomistic”[17] methods of the earlier versions, but work from an idealized understanding of capitalist accumulation and competition.[18] Specifically, the latter incarnations of intersectionality assert that Marxist theorizations of accumulation and competition posit the homogenization of both capitalists and workers, and are thus incapable of explaining gendered and racialized divisions amongst them.
This misunderstanding of the dynamics of the reproduction of capitalist social relations is evident in the work of David Roediger and Elizabeth Esch.[19] They have produced a rich description of how both capitalists and wage workers deploy race—the myth of intrinsic and unchangeable differences amongst humans—to defend and advance their social positions in capitalist societies. They provide a detailed map of both shifting “racial boundaries” within the working class across time; and the persistence of racialization throughout the history of US capitalism. However, racism remains an independent vector of oppression that operates externally to, but in afunctional relationship to capitalist accumulation and competition. Roediger and Esch argue, as does Boeher and others, that the operation of the law of valuehomogenizes labor--- equalizing wages, conditions of work and the like:[20] For them, racism exists because it is functional for capital—as a mechanism to ideologically and politically divide an increasingly homogeneous working class. As do other intersectional theorists, Roediger and Esch deploy a simplistic understanding of capitalist accumulation and competition that leaves them unable to explain how the structure of capitalism both compels andenables[21] capitalists to ideologically and politically differentiate workers whose conditions of life and work are ostensibly becominghomogeneous.[22]
Lise Vogel’s seminal, but long ignored, attempt to construct a unitary theory of gender oppression provides a model for transcending the dilemmas of contingent theories of racial oppression and capitalism. Vogel situates women’s oppressionwithin the real dynamics of capitalist accumulation, which requires the continuous reproduction of capitalism’s “special commodity,” labor-power. There are three aspects to the social reproduction of labor-power: the capacity to work must be reproduced daily (workers must be fed, clothed, etc. to appear at work each day), those who cannot work (the young, the old and the disabled) must be cared for, and the working class must be reproduced inter-generationally. While capitalism has found various ways to organize the daily reproduction of labor-power and the care of non-workers—work-camps, single-sex dormitories, immigration, old-age homes, orphanages, etc.—thegenerational reproduction of labor-power requires both thesocial andbiological reproduction of human beings. All class societies socially organize the biological capacities (childbearing and nursing) that create women’s “differential role in the reproduction of labor-power.” Capitalism takes hold of and transforms the main site of the daily and intergenerational reproduction of labor-power, the family/household, creating “a severe spatial, temporal, and institutional separation between domestic labor and the capitalist production process.”[23] Women’s primary responsibility for the privatized, “domestic” aspects of social reproduction is the matrix for the production of gender oppression.
What follows is an attempt to sketch a unitary or necessity theory of capitalism and racial oppression. We begin with a rigorous understanding of both the necessary dynamics of capitalist reproductionand the radical discontinuity between non-capitalist and capitalist forms of social production. Contrary to most radical and “Marxian” accounts of capitalist accumulation and competition, we will argue they do nothomogenize capitalists and workers. Instead, accumulation and competition necessarily produce heterogeneity of profit rates, labor-processes and wage rates. The dynamics of the capitalist mode of production—market-competition and the continuous development of the productivity of labor through labor-saving technological innovation—cannot explain the emergence and expansion of this form of social labor. The continuing process of “primitive accumulation”—thecreation of capitalist social property relations—requires political-legal coercion and, in many circumstances, does not immediately produce specifically capitalist social relations of production.[24] These social and historical processes create the matrix for the production and reproduction of race—the notion that humanity is divided into distinct groups withunchangeable characteristics that make one groupinherently superior and other groupsinherently inferior—as the “mental road map of lived experience” of both exploiters and exploited under capitalism.
This analysis owes a profound debt to three Marxian thinkers in the Black Radical tradition, whose attempts to grapple with the relationship of capitalism and racial oppression prefigure what I argue here. W.E.B. DuBois is best known for his notion that white working class and popular racism is rooted in a “public and psychological wage” that gives them political rights and social deference. While he used this term only once in his magisterial Black Reconstruction, in most of his other work he roots racist ideology and practices inlabor-market competition. [25] In his analysis of the 1919 St. Louis “race riot”—a white working-class pogrom against newly arrived Black workers—DuBois argued:
If the white workingmen of East St. Louis felt sure that Negro workers would not and could not take the bread and cake from their mouths, their race hatred would never have been translated into murder. If the black workingmen of the South could earn a decent living under decent circumstances at home, they would not be compelled to underbid their white fellows.[26]
Oliver Cromwell Cox’s Race, Class and Caste[27] made the first systematic attempt to analyze the necessary relationship between capitalist exploitation and racial oppression. Cox, despite sharing Robinson’s commercialization model of the origins of capitalism, clearly distinguished between pre-capitalist forms of differentiating humans, in particularcaste, and the distinctively capitalist form,racism.[28] Ruth Wilson Gilmore[29] deploys an analysis of the reserve army of labor since the 1970s to reveal the actual social basis for the expansion of racialized incarceration in the United States. Her insights into the capitalist management of growing “relative surplus populations” informs our analysis of the necessary relationship between capitalist accumulation and racial oppression.
Accumulation, Competition, “Primitive Accumulation”
Contrary to most interpretations of capitalism and its origins, including many ostensibly Marxist accounts, capitalist reproduction through competition and accumulation and the process by which capitalism emerges are not elements of the “material” economic “base” which in turn determines the “social superstructure” of culture and politics.[30] Contrary to notions that trans-historical processes—market competition, technological innovation, and plunder—produce and structure capitalism, capitalist accumulation and competition and “primitive accumulation” are social and historical processes.[31] Put simply, specific social property relations—relations amongst human beings (class relations) and between humans and nature (labor processes)—shape the social dynamics of any form of social production and co-constitute the political and cultural relations, including specific forms of oppression, of these forms of production.
Under capitalism, both producers and non-producers must reproduce themselves through market competition. On the one hand, the capitalists’ continued possession of the means of production requires compelling workers to produce at or below the socially average necessary labor-time—they must “sell to survive.” On the other hand, the dispossession of workers from non-market forms of subsistence makes them dependent on wage labor for survival, and easily hired and fired by capital. These social property relations, as we will argue in detail below, do not lead to economic equilibrium or the homogenization of profits rates, labor-processes, or wage rates. Instead, they give rise to the uniquely capitalist dynamics of accumulation and real competition through the uneven and combined mechanization of production—processes that necessarily produce heterogeneous social classes. “Primitive accumulation” is not a process of spreading markets, technological innovation running up against the “obstacle” of “outdated” social relations or simple geographic expansion, plunder and looting of the non-capitalist world. Instead, primitive accumulation—the transformation of means of production into capital and of direct producers into wage labor—is the unintended consequence of the struggle between non-capitalist exploiters and exploited attempting to reproduce themselves as non-capitalist classes. In sum, the emergence and development of the capitalist “economy” arehistorical and social processes of the creation and reproduction of distinctive social class relations.
Nor are politics and ideology “social superstructures” separate and apart from the “material base.” Instead, these ostensibly “superstructural” elements part of:
…a continuous structure of social relations and forms with varying degrees of distance from the immediate process of production and appropriation, beginning with those relations and forms that constitute the system of production itself. The connections between ‘base’ and superstructure’ can then be traced without great conceptual leaps because they do not represent two essentially different and discontinuous orders of reality.”[32]
From this perspective, ideology is not a free-floating set of cultural ideals or discourses separate and apart from the social relations that constitute social production. Nor is it mere propaganda “imposed” on a passive population through the media, schools and the like; or the equivalent of “doctrine,” a coherent and stable set of beliefs about the world. Instead, ideologies are the “mental road map of lived experience”– the “vocabulary of day-to-day action and experience” shaped by social property relations.[33] These mental road maps change as the lived experience of social relations change through practice and conflict. Put another way, ideological notions and practices, including racial oppression, are “co-constituted” by the reproduction of specific social relations of production and form part of the “internal relations” of different modes of production.[34]
Most Marxists and non-Marxists attribute to Marx a theory of value, accumulation, and competition that homogenizes capital and labor. This reflects neither Marx’s mature theory inCapital nor the actual history of capitalism. Instead, the reproduction of capitalism does nothomogenize but constantlydifferentiates capitalists and workers.[35] The operation the law of value—where the exchange-value of different commodities are expressed in the amount of socially average abstract labor time required to produce them—does not depend upon thehomogenization of labor. Rather, it is capitalist competition and accumulation that allows the products of fundamentallydifferentconcrete human labor-processes to exchange asequivalents byabstracting from those concrete differences.[36]
The notions that accumulation and competition homogenize conditions of production confuse Marx’s account ofreal competition with neo-classical economics’idealized vision of competition. “Perfect competition,” where numerous firms are passive “price-takers” and any firm’s market advantage is temporary at best, produces uniform profit rates and wages. This vision of competition makes the existing economic order appear efficient and just.Real capitalist competition has little to do with the dream world of neo-classical economics. Real competition is fought through what Marx called the “heavy artillery of fixed capital”—constant technological innovation, taking the form of the increasing mechanization of production—for market share won at the expense of other producers. According to Shaikh,[37] “real competition, antagonistic by nature and turbulent by nature… is as different from so-called perfect competition as war is from ballet.”
Real competition and accumulation through increasing the mechanization of production creates heterogeneity among capitalists and workers. The process of the division of tasks and their mechanization in one branch of production leads to a portion of the workforce being made redundant for capital. This constant replenishment thereserve army of labor, the mass of unemployed and underemployed, not only regulates wages within the boundaries of profitability, but creates the possibility ofheterogeneous labor-processes, profit-rates, and wages between branches of industry. While the increasingly capital-intensive industries enjoy higher profits and the possibility of higher wages, the constant replenishing of the reserve army allows the constant reproduction oflabor-intensive industries with lower profits and lower wages. In other words, “sweated labor” under capitalism is not some atavistic hangover of earlier forms of production, but the necessary consequence of the continued, but necessarily uneven and combined mechanization of production.[38]
The constant generation of the reserve army, with workers experiencing different levels of precarity and desperation, produce workers who have little choice but to accept the worst jobs across the economy. In the presence of the reserve army, the mobility of capital and labor sets limits to, but cannot eliminate, overall wage differentiation. Low wage sectors can avoid raising wages by tapping into pools of desperate workers. Low-wage industries often draw from specific labor-reserves—specific layers of unemployed and underemployed workers whose labor-power is reproduced under distinctive social conditions—in order to maintain their profitability.[39] Migrant workers are a contemporary example of such a distinct reserve army of labor. The physical separation of inter-generational reproduction in the global South and day-to-day reproduction in the global North, allows capitalists in low wage industries to pay wages below the costs of reproduction of labor-power in the global North.[40] “Undocumented” immigrants’ lack of the most minimal political rights enjoyed by “citizens” intensifies the precarious conditions of the social reproduction of this segment of the reserve army of labor.
Competition within and between industries also necessarily differentiates labor-processes, profits and wage rates. In the competitive “war of all against all,” firms with older investments in fixed capital have difficulty reducing unit costs and raising profit margins and rates. However, they cannot abandon these investments immediately in favor of new and more efficient methods. Capitalist investment in buildings, machinery, and the like create barriers to immediately adopting new techniques orexiting a branch of production. Capitals with older and less efficient fixed capital, thenon-regulating capitals, haveno choice but to remain in business until their investments are amortized. They compete with “state of the art” capitals, theregulating capitals, by paying below average wages, and intensifying work through speed-up, sub-division of tasks, and other means of increasing absolute surplus-value extraction.[41]
Contrary to contemporary usage, “primitive accumulation” is not simply a process of the accumulation of wealth through plunder, slavery, and colonialism.[42] Marx explicitly rejected this notion in Capital, arguing that it reduces the process of primitive accumulation to a morality tale in which “the frugal elite” accumulate wealth through means fair and foul, while “the lazy rascals” are left with no choice but to labor for their betters.[43] Means of production and subsistence become capital only when means of production are transformed into a commodity whose possession requires successful market competition. It is only on the basis of new social relations of production that the wealth appropriated through the colonization and plunder is accumulated as productive capital rather than transformed into pre-capitalist forms of surplus extraction.[44]
Primitive accumulation necessarily requires non-market compulsion.[45] All non-capitalist forms of production are based on the direct producers’ effective possession of means of production or subsistence, and the non-producers use of non-market coercion to appropriate surpluses from the direct producers. Prior to capitalism, the reproduction of both the exploiters and exploited was not predicated on successful market competition through specialization, technical innovation and accumulation, but instead on these classes’ political organization. As a result, neither the growth of markets nor the development of labor-productivity could displace non-capitalist social relations and replace them with those of capitalism. Instead, the deployment of legal and political force was necessary to force producers to become market dependent (the imposition of capitalist ground rent, public land systems, etc.) and to compel the expropriated to sell their labor-power (enforcing the closure of access to common lands through state violence, taxations, forced labor and various forms of servitude, etc.) Both the original process in England in the sixteenth century, and the uneven and combined geographic expansion of capitalism globally in the five centuries afterwards was “written in the annals of mankind in letters of blood and fire.”[46]
Capitalism and Racist Ideology and Practices
Why do the creation and reproduction of capitalist class relations necessarily lead to racialization—the division of humanity into distinct groups withunchangeable characteristics that make one group inherently superior and others inherently inferior? Accumulation and competition give rise to a contradictory lived experience for both capitalists and workers. Capitalism is the first form of social labor in human history where exploitation takes place through whatappears to be theexchange of equivalents in the labor-market.[47] Rather than relying on personal domination or other forms of extra-economic coercion, capitalists and workers confront each other on the labor-market as owners of distinctive commodities—capitalists own the means of production, workers their labor-power. Capitalists purchase the workers’ capacity to work generally at its value—the historically constituted social conditions of the reproduction of labor-power. As capitalistconsume labor-power—put workers to work in labor-processes under the command of capital—workers are compelled to produce valuein excess of the value of their wages.
The buying and selling of labor-power gives rise to a very specific vocabulary of lived experience that spontaneously disguises exploitation and produces the notion of theequality of all human beings. InValue, Price, and Profit,[48] Marx argued that under slavery all labor appears unpaid, and under serfdom the division between paid and unpaid labor is clearly visible in the division of crops and labor. By contrast, under capitalism “even the unpaid labor seems to bepaid labor” because “the nature of the whole transaction is completely masked by theintervention of a contract…” InCapital, Marx identified how this produces a distinctive ideology, “the sphere of circulation or commodity exchange, within whose boundaries the sale and purchase of labor-power goes on, is in fact a very Eden of the innate rights of man. It is the exclusive realm of Freedom, Equality, Property, and Bentham.”[49]
However, once we leave the idealized world of commodity exchange, we enter the real world of capitalist production, accumulation, and competition, which necessarily producessubstantial inequalities—between capital and labor, within the working class and between societies in the capitalist world economy. In pre-capitalist societies, human inequality wasassumed to be part of the “order of things;” inscribed in relations of personal dependence and extra-economic coercion. By contrast, the actuality of inequality must beexplained under capitalism in a way that iscompatible with the notion that human beingsshould be free and equal. This requires are-naturalization of difference—the division of humanity into groups withunchangeable characteristics making some inherently superior, others inferior. Only if some people are viewed as and treated as less than “fully human” can either capitalists or groups of competing workers make sense of a society where all appear to be equal, but there is real inequality between and within classes.
A similarly contradictory lived experience marks the process of the geographic expansion of capitalism.[50] On the one hand, capitalist imperialism presents itself as “universalizing” the “benefits of civilization” -- the “fair and equal exchange” of the market and the blessing of capitalist “improvement,” the development of the productivity of labor through technical innovation and accumulation. Unfortunately for capital, the subordination of non-capitalist producers to market compulsion cannot be achieved on the basis of “fair and equal exchange” or “out-producing backward producers,” because both non-capitalist exploiters and exploited have effective possession of means of production and subsistence. As a result, race becomes central to the “mental road map of lived experience” that explains and justifies the violent expropriation of non-capitalist producers and the establishment of capitalist social property relations.[51]
Racial and gender differentiation are the most common ways both capitalists and workers navigate the contradictory lived experience of capitalist development. Gender differences are ideologically reduced to biology—gender is equated with sexual differentiation-- which purportedly explains women’sinherent inferiority to me. While race has no biological existence, the process of racialization socially constructs differences that are purported to be permanent and unchangeable.[52] Racialization naturalizes differences in physical appearances, religion, language, and the like.[53] Racist ideology, with its notion of inherent andunchangeable relations of inequality provides a potent mental road map for both capitalists and workers of the contradictory lived experience of the creation and reproduction of capitalist social property relations.
The History of Racism
If racism is a central “vocabulary of the lived experience” of the creation and reproduction of capitalism, then it must have a distinct history. The notion that race and racism existtrans-historically, at least since European antiquity is at the heart of Cedric Robinson’sBlack Marxism.[54] Other scholars[55] have rooted Ancient ‘racism’ in the belief that differences between “civilized” and “barbaric” groups were rooted in environmental factors that became inheritable. However, even proponents of a Greco-Roman racism admit that the inheritance of acquired characteristics were not seen as“constant and stable”[56] from one generation to another. Put another way, a new physical environment could easily produce new social and behavioral characteristics—making themfluid and flexible. In addition, those claiming the existence of racialization in classical antiquity have not demonstrated that certain groups wereexcluded from political life if they paid rent, taxes, or tribute to their rulers. In fact, there is considerable evidence of Africans, in particular, being integrated into the Greek and Roman states as soldiers and public officials.[57]
Before capitalism, humanity was differentiated by religion (“heathens and believers”) and kinship-community (“strangers and neighbors/kin”). Both tended to be highly flexible and changeable through conversion, adoption, and the like. In almost all non-capitalist forms of social labor, class exploitation was indistinguishable from political-legal unfreedom, making inequality appear “natural.” Pre-capitalist imperialism did not generally disrupt the direct producers’ effective possession of means of production and subsistence, but transferred lordship or politically regulated trade monopolies from one group of non-capitalist exploiters to another.[58] Thus, the fluid character of “othering” provided an adequate understanding of the lived experience of these social and historical processes. Under capitalism, race is a form of human differentiation where distinguishing characteristics become unchangeable. According to Go,[59] “it is not that capitalism was built on prior racial differences; rather, capitalism served to racialize the preexisting ethnic division of labor, turning religious, cultural, or linguistic differences into ‘racial’ ones to legitimate its new exploitative strictures… racialization… was a part of modern capitalism, not its precursor.”
There is evidence that an early form of “proto-racism” emerged in one region of pre-capitalist Europe.[60] In late fourteenth and early fifteenth century Castile and Aragon, the conquering Christian monarchs forcibly expelled the previous Muslim rulers and those Jewish bankers and merchants who failed to convert to Christianity. By the mid-fifteenth century, as competition for venal offices in the new Absolutist monarchies intensified, Christians began to exclude Muslims and Jews who had converted to Christianity (conversos or “New Christians”) from the ranks of the nobility and key public offices. The claim was that these converts lacked “purity of blood” (limpieza de sange), and detailed genealogical records demonstrating that families had been Christians for several generations became a prerequisite for social advancement. With the unification of Spanish absolutism in 1492, the expulsion of Jews and Muslims who refused to convert, and the exclusion ofconversos became generalized.[61] Despite its emergence in late feudal Iberia, the generalization of race did not occur across European Absolutism, where the continued reality of non-market coercion made human inequality continue to appear to benatural.
Racial oppression in its modern form was crystallized two centuries later during the English capitalist colonization of Virginia.[62] When legal unfreedom is the typical status of the laboring classes, as it was in most pre-capitalist societies including Virginia before the late seventeenth century, inequality wasassumed. It was only when all other forms of bonded labor, in particular indentured servitude, were abolished in early eighteenth-century Virginia, that the enslavement of people of African descent needed to beexplained andjustified. The notion of race was systematized to justify the unfreedom of Africans alone in a society wherelegal freedom and equality were becoming the norm. According to Fields:
By the Age of Revolution, English society and its American offspring [shared-CP] … the assumption that the individual is the proprietor of his own person… [This notion—CP] had advanced sufficiently to make bondage a condition for calling for justification and to narrow the basis on which such a justification might rest. Slavery by then could be neither taken for granted nor derived from self-evident general principles. Pro-slavery and antislavery publicists… unconsciously collaborated in locating that basis of the slaves’ presumed incapacity from freedom, an incapacity that crystallized into a racial one and all of its subsequent pseudo-biological trappings.” [63]
While plantation slavery in Virginia was a non-capitalist form of production,[64] it emerged as part of the first process of capitalist colonization.[65] The break through to capitalist agriculture in England in the sixteenth century gave rise to a mass consumer market among prosperous capitalist tenant farmers. Merchants operating outside the declining system of royal monopolies sought to supply this market, initiating plantation production of sugar and tobacco in the English Caribbean and southern North American mainland. While the new merchants were unable to establish capitalist social relations in their colonies, the colonies were extensions of the first capitalist society—the first society where juridical-legal freedom and equality was becoming the norm.
Forms and Variations of Racism
Race and racism did not disappear with the abolition of New World slavery, but instead becomes generalized across the capitalist world. The specific terms of racist ideology, whatspecific characteristics made some groups superior and others inferior, and the forms of racial oppression varied according to thespecific historical forms capitalist social relations and their geographic expansion took. Unfortunately, many critical social scientists have attempted to grasp these variations through the notion of “racial formations.”[66] These typologies often take on a ‘life of their own,” leading to attempts to assign distinctive dynamics to each idealized “racial formation” and a loss of the historical specificity of each set of racist ideologies and practices. Instead, we need to proceed from the abstract understanding of the necessity of racial oppression to capitalist reproduction and expansion, and then move to the concrete, historical specificity of racial oppression in specific, historically constituted capitalist societies.
For example, in the aftermath of the abolition of US plantation slavery, the forms of racism changed because “there is, after all, a profound difference in social meaning between a planter who experiences black people as ungrateful, untrustworthy, and half-witted slaves and a planter who experiences black people as undisciplined, irregular and refractory employees.”[67] Through the history of capitalist imperialism, the racialization of indigenous populations varied according to whether these people were forcibly expelled to make room for “white” settlers (US Native Americans, Australian “Aborigines,” Palestinians, etc.) or were compelled, under varying degrees of legal coercion, to labor for wages for their conquerors (South Africa, part of colonial India, most of Latin America since the early twentieth century, etc.) In the former case, the indigenous populations are seen as inherently incapable of “improving” land in a capitalist manner and must be expropriated and expelled to make room for “civilized” farmers and workers. In the latter case, the indigenous people are seen as having inherently different requirements for social reproduction and commitment to “steady work.”
Under specifically capitalist accumulation and competition, the differentiation of capital and labor spontaneously generates the notion that different groups of workers have unchangeable characteristics, making some inherently more or less “reliable” workers.Both capitalists and workers, especially when working class organizations like unions are weak, utilize race as a way of ordering the access to employment. The constant subdivision and mechanization of tasks characteristic of capitalism, creates a mass of workers in both the active and reserve armies of labor who can perform almost any specific job.[68] Workers and capitalists invent fictional racial “characteristics” to determine who are the most “reliable” and “efficient” workers for different tasks.[69] At the center of this process of constructing a racial “roadmap of lived experience” is the notion that different “races” have inherently different costs of social reproduction and capacities to produce different quanta of surplus value (inherently different levels of skill, intelligence, motivation, and productivity).
English capitalists in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century viewed the Irish, who were being rapidly expropriated by English landlords, as ignorant and crude peasants whose costs of reproduction and capacity for “steady” and skilled work was less than those of English workers. The Irish were deemed suitable only for “pick and shovel” work on the docks, canal and railroad construction, and the most deskilled positions in manufacturing.[70] In the US, capitalists developed an elaborate racial hierarchy of costs of reproduction and work capacities for the Irish in the early nineteenth century and the varied southern and eastern European immigrants in the late nineteenth and twentieth century.[71] As Blacks are expelled from southern agriculture before and during World War I, their purported lower costs of social reproduction and lesser capacities for “disciplined labor’ justified their assignment to the least desirable, lowest skill and most poorly paid work in industry. The racialization of the labor-market is evident in the global South as well, as British and later Arab capitalists assigned different costs of reproduction and laboring capacities to different groups of migrant workers in the Gulf ports.[72]
The process of the racialization of the labor market and reserve armies does not proceed simply “from above”—through the agency of capitalists—but “from below” – through the activity of workers when collective action and organization against capital does not appear viable. Working class racism is rooted in the contradictory position of workers under capitalism: “workers are not only collective producers with a common interest in taking collective control over social production. They are alsoindividual sellers of labor power in conflict with each other over jobs, promotions, etc.”[73] As competing sellers of labor power, workers are open to the appeal of politics that pit them against other workers—especially workers in a weaker social position. For example, Skilled artisanal workers in the early nineteenth century US attempt to socially construct themselves as “white” to protect themselves from the pressures of the reserve army of labor and the threat of being easily replaced as capital deskilled their work. Fears of impoverization and deskilling fueled antebellum northern white skilled workers projection “onto Black workers what they still desired in terms of the imagined absence of alienation, even as they bridled at being treated as slaves or ‘white n*ggers.’”[74] By the mid-nineteenth century, competition between for unskilled work in northern cities led to racist pogroms by Irish workers against African Americans, culminating in the bloody “draft riots” in New York and other cities during the Civil War.[75] As the mass migration of African-Americans to the northern cities began before World War I, competition among workers exploded in the “race riots” of 1919, and again in the wave of “hate strikes” during World War II.[76] In the past four decades, the support of a minority of older, white workers for right-wing politicians, beginning with Reagan and culminating in Trump, reflect a similar dynamic[77]. Satnam Virdee[78] traces similar racialized competition stimulating working class racism in Britain in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
Multi-racial working-class unity will not be produced spontaneously-- it will require the rebuilding a culture and organization of solidarity among workers.[79] Clearly, struggles for universal, class wide demands—higher wages, greater job security, health care (“Medicare for All”) and pensions not tied to employment, etc.—reduce competition among workers and are a necessary, but not sufficient conditions for building a multi-racial workers’ movement. The mainstream of the industrial union movement of the 1930s and 1940s made “color-blind” appears to workers, allowing racial divisions to deepen and contributing to the failure to organize the southern US.[80]Race-specific demands like defunding and disarming the police, ending housing and residential segregation, plant and industry-wide seniority,[81] affirmative action in hiring and promotion, full citizenship rights for all immigrants upon arrival, an end to racial harassment and discrimination on the job, and the like will be essential to building multiracial working class solidarity. The experience of the Brotherhood of Sleeping Car Porters, the Negro Labor Congress, the Negro American Labor Council, and Black and Latino caucuses in unions in the 1960s and 1970s demonstrate that a multiracial workers’ movement also requires self-organization by workers of color within the broader labor movement. Finally, non-work place movements against racism, like the uprising of 2020, have radicalized workers and promoted multiracial unity. Put simply,effective class organization and politics—forging working class unity among a racially heterogeneous class—must includeanti-racism.
Bibliography
Activist Roundtable 2020, “Socialists and the Uprising Against Racism,” Tempest 5 August.https://www.tempestmag.org/2020/08/socialists-and-the-uprising/.
Allen, Theodore 1994, The Invention of the White Race, Volume 1:Racial Oppression and Social Control, London: Verso Books.
Allen, Theodore 1997, The Invention of the White Race, Volume 2:The Origin of Racial Oppression in Anglo-America, London: Verso Books.
Arruzza, Cinzia 2014, “Remarks on Gender” Viewpoint Magazine 2 September.[https://www.viewpointmag.com/2014/09/02/remarks-on-gender/] and
Arruzza, Cinzia 2015, “Logic or History? The Political Stakes of Marxist-Feminist Theory” Viewpoint Magazine, 23 June [https://www.viewpointmag.com/2015/06/23/logic-or-history-the-political-stakes-of-marxist-feminist-theory/]
Bernstein, Ivar 2010, The New York City Draft Riots: Their Significant for American Society and Politics in the Age of the Civil War, Lincoln, NB: Bison Books.
Bhandar, Brenna 2018, Colonial Lives of Property: Law, Land and Racial Regimes of Ownership, Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Bhattacharya, Tithi 2017, “Introduction” in in Social Reproduction Theory: Remapping Class, Recentering Oppression, edited by T. Bhattacharya, London: Pluto Press.
Bhattacharyya, Gargi 2018. Rethinking Racial Capitalism: Questions of Reproduction and Survival, New York: Rowman & Littlefield.
Blackburn, Robin 1997, The Making of New World Slavery: From the Baroque to the Modern, 1492-1800, London: Verso Brooks.
Bohrer, Ashley, 2019, Marxism and Intersectionality: Race, Gender, Class, and Sexuality Under Contemporary Capitalism, Bellefield: Transcript Verlag.
Bonnett, Alastair 1998, “Who Was White? The Disappearance of non-European White Identities and the Formation of European Racial Whiteness,” Ethnic and Racial Studies 21, 6 (November), 1029-1055.
Botwinick, Howard 2018, Persistent Inequalities: Wage Differentials Under Capitalist Competition, Chicago: Haymarket Books.
Braverman, Harry 1974, Labor and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation of Labor in the 20th Century, New York: Monthly Review Press.
Brenner, Robert P. 1977, “The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of Neo-Smithian Marxism,” New Left Review I/104 (July-August): 25-91.
Brenner, Robert P. 1993, Merchants and Revolution: Commercial Change, Political Conflict, and London’s Overseas traders, 1550-1653, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Brenner, Johanna and Robert Brenner 1981, “Reagan, the Right and the Working Class” Against the Current (Old Series) 1,2 (Winter): 29-35.
Burden-Stelly, Charisse, 2020, “Caste Does Not Explain Race” Boston Review (December 14)https://bostonreview.net/articles/charisse-burden-stelly-tk/
Buroway, Michael, 1976, “The Functions and Reproduction of Migrant Labor: Comparative Material from Southern Africa and the United States,” American Journal of Sociology 81, 5 (March): 1050-1087.
Callinicos, Alex 2006, Making History: Agency, Structure, and Change in Social Theory, Chicago: Haymarket Books.
Chibber, Vivek 2013, Post-Colonial Theory and the Specter of Capital, London: Verso Books.
Chibber, Vivek 2017, “Rescuing Class from the Cultural Turn” Catalyst 1;1, 27-56.
Chibber, Vivek 2020, “Debating the ‘Defund the Police’ Language,” Jacobin Show 11 December.https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=qbR3wmKavng.
Cohen, G.A. 1978, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cox, Oliver C 1948, Race, Class and Caste, New York: Doubleday.
Du Bois, W.E.B. 1920, Darkwater: Voices from Within the Veil, New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company
Du Bois, W.E.B., 1935, Black Reconstruction: An Essay Toward a History of the Part Which Black Folk Played in the Attempt to Reconstruct Democracy in America, 1860-1880, New York: Harcourt Brace and Company.
Evans, Jessica 2018, “Colonialism, Racism, and the Transition to Capitalism in Canada” in Case Studies in the Origins of Capitalism edited by X, LaFrance and C. Post, London: Palgrave.
Ferguson, Susan and David McNally, “Precarious Migrants: Gender, Race and the Social Reproduction of a Global Working Class,” in Socialist Register 2015: Transforming Classes, edited by L. Panitch and G. Albo, New York: Monthly Review Press.
Fields, Barbara Jeanne 1982, “Ideology and Race in American History,” Region, Race and Reconstruction: Essays in Honor of C. Vann Woodward edited by in J. Morgan Kousser and James M. McPherson, New York: Oxford University Press.
Fields, Barbara Jeanne 1990, “Slavery, Race and Ideology in the United States of America” New Left Review I/181 (May-June): 93-118.
Friedman, Samuel R. 1984, Structure, Process and the Labor Market” in Labor Economics: Modern Views, edited by William Darity, Jr., Boston: Kluwer-Nijhoff Publishing, 1984.
Gilmore, Ruth Wilson 2007, Golden Gulag: Prisons, Surplus, Crisis, and Opposition in Globalizing California, Berkeley: University of California Press,
Guastella, Dustin, 2020, “To End Police Violence Fund Public Good and Raise Wages,” Nonsite.Org July 9.https://nonsite.org/policing-symposium/.
Go, Julian 2020, “Three Tensions in the Theory of Racial Capitalism” Sociological Theory 1-10.https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/0735275120979822?casa_token=pai-oVT9ztIAAAAA:aPRujn9fOh9Fn66kjIhxt6cuyxTFvEOxpYrEE0_0_0EAq-AyaHFuYmOfgydd66RZwvD0Rb1deFc
Goldfield, Michael 2020, The Southern Key: Class, Race & Radicalism in the 1930s & 1940s, New York: Oxford University Press
Hill, Patricia Collins 2000, Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment, New York: Routledge
Hall, Stuart 1980 “Race, Articulation and Societies Structured in Dominance” in Sociological Theories: Race and Colonialism, Paris: UNESCO
Ignatiev, Noel 1995, How the Irish Became White, New York: Routledge.
Haider, Asad 2018, Mistaken Identity: Race and Class in the Age of Trump, London: Verso Books.
Hartmann, Heidi, 1979, “The Unhappy Marriage of Marxism and feminism: Towards A More Progressive Union,” Capital & Class 3,2:1-33.
Harvey, David 2014, Seventeen Contradictions and the End of Capitalism, New York: Oxford University Press.
Hellerstein Judith, and David Neumark 2004, “Workplace Segregation in the United States: Race, Ethnicity and Skill’ NBER Working Paper 11599, Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Economic Research.http://www.nber.org/papers/w11599.
Hering Torres,Marx S., Maria Elena Martinez and David Nirenberg (eds.) 2012, Race and Blood in the Iberian World, Zurich: LIT Verlag.
Isaac, Benjamin 2004, The Invention of Racism in Classical Antiquity, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Isaac, Benjamin 2009, ““Racism: A Rationalization of Prejudice in Greece and Rome” inThe Origin of Racism in the West edited by B. Isaac, J. Ziegler and M. Eliav-Feldon, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Jaffe, Aaron 2020, Social Reproduction Theory and the Socialist Horizon, London: Pluto Press.
Khalili, Laleh 2020, Sinews of War and Trade: Shipping and Capitalism in the Arabian Peninsula, London: Verso Books.
Lebowitz, Michael 2006, “The Politics of Assumption, the Assumption of Politics” Historical Materialism, 14:2: 29-47.
LaFrance, Xavier 2021, “The Vacuity of Structurelessness; Situating Agency and Structure in Exploitative and Alienated Social Relations,” Historical Materialism 929.3: 84-106.
Lentin, Alana 2020, Why Race Still Matters, Cambridge, England: Polity Press.
Lewis, Holly 2016, The Politics of Everybody: Feminism, Queer Theory, and Marxism at the Intersection, London: Zed Books.
Marx, Karl 1910, Value, Price and Profit, Chicago, CH Kerr.
Marx, Karl 1976, Capital, Volume I, Harmondsworth, England: Penguin Books.
Mason, Patrick L. 1995, “Race, Competition and Differential Wages,” Cambridge Journal of Economics 19: 545-567
McNally, David 2015, “The Dialectics of Unity and Difference in the Constitution of Wage-Labor: On Internal Relations and Working-Class Formation” Capital & Class, 39:1, 131-146
McNally, David 2017, “Intersections and Dialectics: Critical Reconstructions in Social Reproduction Theory” in Social Reproduction Theory, pp. 94-111
Melchor, Cody R. 2019, “First as Tragedy, Then As Farce: WEB DuBois, Left-Wing Radicalism, and the Problem of Interracial Unionism” Critical Sociology 46, 7-8: 1041-1055.
Nelson, Bruce 2001, Divided We Stand: American Workers and the Struggle for Black Equality, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Morgan, Edmund S., 1975 American Slavery, American Freedom: The Ordeal of Colonial Virginia, New York: W.W. Norton & Co.
Nirenberg, David 2009, “Was There Race Before Modernity? The Examples of ‘Jewish’ Blood in Late Medieval Spain” in The Origin of Racism in the West, edited by B. Isaac, J. Ziegler and M. Eliav-Feldon.
Omi, Michael and Howard Winant, 2015, Racial Formation in the United States, London: Routledge.
Post, Charles 2016, “The Separation of the ‘Economic’ and the ‘Political’ Under Capitalism: ‘Capital-centric Marxism’ and the Capitalist State” Verso Blog (January 14)https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2345-charles-post-the-separation-of-the-economic-and-the-political-under-capitalism-capital-centric-marxism-and-the-capitalist-state
Post, Charles 2012, The American Road to Capitalism: Studies in Class Structure, Economic Development and Political Conflict, 1620-1877, Chicago: Haymarket Books.
Post, Charles 2017, “The Roots of Trumpism” Cultural Dynamics (May 24)https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0921374017709229
Post, Charles 2021, “Structure and Agency in Historical Materialism: A Response to Knafo and Teschke,” Historical Materialism 29.3: 107-124
Queneau, Hevre 2009, “Trends in Occupational Segregation by Race and Ethnicity in the USA: Evidence from Detailed Data” Applied Economics Letters, 16: 1347-1350.
Raju, Archishman 2021 “At The Brink of a New World System: Imperialism, Race and Caste” MR Online (August 15)https://mronline.org/2021/08/15/at-the-brink-of-a-new-world-system-imperialism-race-and-caste/#edn_5
Roberts, William Clare 2017, “What Was Primitive Accumulation? Reconstructing the Origins of a Critical Concept” European Journal of Political Theory, 19 (4): 532-552.
Robinson, Cedric 1983, Black Marxism: The Making of the Black Radical Tradition, Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Roediger, David and Elizabeth Esch 2012, The Production of Difference: Race and Management of Labor in US History, New York: Oxford University Press.
Roediger, David 2005, Working Toward Whiteness: How America’s Immigrants Became White—The Strange Journey from Ellis Island to the Suburbs, New York: Basic Books.
Roediger, David 2019, Class, Race, and Marxism, London: Verso Books.
Shaikh, Anwar 2016, Capitalism: Competition, Conflict, and Crises, New York: Oxford University Press.
Snowden, Frank M. 1983, Before Color Prejudice: The Ancient View of Blacks,
Steinberg, Steven 1989, The Ethnic Myth: Race, Ethnicity and Class in America, Boston: Beacon Press.
Virdee, Satnam 2014, Racism, Class and the Racialized Outsider, London: Palgrave.
Virdee, Satnam 2018, “Racialized Capitalism: An Account of Its contested Origins and Consolidation” The Sociological Review 67,1: 3-27.
Vogel, Lise 2013, Marxism and the Oppression of Women: Toward a Unitary Theory, Chicago: Haymarket Books.
Wallerstein, Immanuel 1974. The Modern World-System I:Capitalist Agriculture and the Origins of the European World-Economy in the Sixteenth Century, New York: Academic Press
Wilkerson, Isabel 2020, Caste: The Origins of Our Discontent, New York: Random House.
Wolfe, Patrick 2016, Trace of History: Elementary Structures of Race, London: Verso Books.
Wolfinger, James 2009, “World War II Hate Strikes” in The Encyclopedia of Strikes in American History, edited by A. Brenner, B. Day and I Ness, Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe.
Wood, Ellen Meiksins 1995, Democracy Against Capitalism: Renewing Historical Materialism, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wood, Ellen Meiksins 2002, The Origins of Capitalism: A Longer View, London: Verso Books.
Wood, Ellen Meiksins 2003, Empire of Capital, London: Verso Books.
[1] The author would like to thank two anonymous reviewers, the editors of Historical Materialism, Tithi Bhattacharya, Howard Botwinick, Robert Brenner, David Camfield, Sue Ferguson, Todd Gordon, Kate Doyle-Griffiths, Asad Haider, Paul Heideman, Aaron Jaffe, David McNally, Kim Moody, Richard Seymour, and Lise Vogel, for their comments on earlier versions of this essay. I want to acknowledge, as well, the participants in my “Capitalism, Race and Class” seminar at the CUNY Graduate Center in the Fall of 2016 and Spring of 2020, and in the Graduate Center Political Economy Workshop in November 2018 where many of these ideas were discussed. A special thanks as well to Satnam Virdee, with whom I have debated these issues in other venues. This essay is dedicated to the memory of James A. Geschwender (1933-2020), who taught me how to think about race and class when I was his graduate student at Binghamton.
[2] 2018.
[3]Activist Roundtable, 2020
[4] Chibber 2020 and Guastella 2020.
[5] 1983.
[6] 1995, Chapter 9.
[7] Wallerstein 1974. For a thorough theoretical and historical critique of this approach, see Brenner 1977 and Wood 2002.
[8] Go 2020, pp. 3-4 makes a similar point.
[9] 1995 p. 259.
[10] Arruzza 2015 and 2015.
[11] Hartman 1979
[12] 2000.
[13] 2019.
[14] 2013, Chapter 2.
[15] 2016, pp. 273-274.
[16] 2017, p 17.
[17] McNally 2017.
[18] Jaffe 2020, Chapter 2020.
[19] 2012.
[20] Roediger and Esch’s understanding of value theory, accumulation, and competition are drawn from Lebowitz 2006.
[21] The notion that structures both compel and enable agents to act in determinant ways is drawn from Callinicos 2006.
[22] Julian Go’s attempt to resolve the tensions in Robinson’s account of racial capitalism suffers from a similar problem. Go deploys David Harvey’s (2014) distinction between “Marx’s theory of capital and histheory of capitalism.” The theory of “capital” in theGrundrisse andCapital works at level of abstraction that cannot account for “categories of race, gender, or ethnicity… because they are too concrete.” (Go 2020, p. 5) By contrast, Marx’s theory of “capitalism” refers to attempts to deploy his theory of “capital” to explain concrete historical developments, including racial oppression. However, Go argues that the relationship of capitalism and racism remain historical and contingent, because it is not possible “to deduce, from the categories of Marx’s theory [of Capital—CP], the necessity of racism or racial differentiations in society.” Harvey’s distinction between a “theory of capital” and a “theory of capitalism” confuses scientific abstraction with the construction of ideal types, which makes a rigorous relationship between theory and history impossible. See Post 2021 for a more detailed exposition of these issues in another context.
[23] Vogel 2013, pp. 151,159.
[24] Legally coerced wage labor continues to be reproduced through capitalist accumulation and competition, in particular in branches of social production where capital relies on highly skilled labor or must pay wages often below the cost of social reproduction to remain competitive and profitable. See Post 2016.
[25] DuBois 1920, Chapter IV. See Melchor 2019 for a discussion of DuBois’ belief that labor-market competition made interracial labor unionism impossible in the US prior to World War II.
[26] 1920, pp. 66-67.
[27] 1948.
[28] Drawing on the work of Cox, Raju (2021) makes a powerful critique of recent attempts to equate caste and racial oppression. Charissee Burden-Stelly (2020) defends Cox’s rejection of the equation of race and caste against Isabel Wilkerson (2020).
[29] 2007, pp. 70-78. Bhattacharyya’s (2018, p. 5) analysis of racial capitalism, despite its reliance on notions of intersectionality, also highlight the way in which capitalist accumulation produces “edge populations” of the unemployed and underemployed globally, whose “racialization… arises retrospectively as a result of marginalization from structures of production and/or the formal labor market… the fiction of race springs up, conveniently and almost spontaneously, to give rationale to the exigencies of capital.”
[30] This version of Marxism, which is rooted in the “systematization” of Marxism by the Second International, continues to shape the approach of both “productive forces” Marxists like G.A. Cohen (1980) and “structural” Marxist of the Althusserian school. This approach mars Hall’s (1980) provocative, but ultimately disappointing attempt to theorize racism.
[31] See Wood 1995, Part I and LaFrance 2021, pp. 85-92.
[32] Wood 1995, pp.25-26.
[33] Our approach to ideology is indebted to the work of Fields, 1990, pp. 110-113.
[34] McNally 2015.
[35] Shaikh 2016, Botwinick 2018
[36] A similar point, derived from Shaikh’s work, is made in Chibber 2013 pp. 133-137, 145-147.
[37] 2016, p. 14.
[38] Botwinick 2018, Chapter 3.
[39] Friedman 1984.
[40] The original formulation of the physical separation of inter-generational and day-to-day reproduction of labor power as the basis of migratory labor system was in Buroway 1976. For a recent deployment of this argument in social reproduction theory see Ferguson and McNally 2014.
[41]This argument should not be confused with ‘dual economy’ theories that posit a “core” with permanently higher profits and wages than the “peripheral” regions of the economy. See Botwinick 2018, Chapters 5-7 for a detailed argument on how the “turbulent regulation” of profit rates, profit margins and wage rates through real capitalist competition prevent any branch of production or individual capital from permanently retaining its “core” position
[42] For a thorough review and critique of the recent literature on primitive accumulation see Roberts 2017.
[43] Marx 1976, p. 873.
[44] Blackburn 1997, Chapter XII details how the profits from Absolutist France’s slave colonies flowed into the purchase of feudal estates and venal office, while only the profits from capitalist England’s’ slave colonies were accumulated as productive capital.
[45] Brenner 1977 and Wood 2002.
[46] Marx 1976, p. 875.
[47] Marx 1976, Chapter 6.
[48] 1910 pp. 83-86.
[49] 1976 p. 280.
[50] This is account of specifically capitalist imperialism is based on Wood 2003, Chapters 4-6.
[51] Jessica Evans (2018), working from a similar understanding of capitalist imperialism, analyzes how the Canadian transition to capitalist agriculture in the mid-nineteenth century led to the racialization of the indigenous people as a group “incapable” of “improving” landed property. Bonnett 1998 traces how European imperialist expansion transformed non-European forms of differentiating people, racializing non-Europeans as non-white and inherently inferior. Other works, which do not share our understanding of capitalist imperialism have produced insightful descriptions of the ways in which capitalist colonization has led to the racialization of non-Europeans in a variety of frameworks. See Bhandar 2018, Bhattacharrya 2018, Lentin 2020, Wolfe 2016.
[52] Such “permanent and unchangeable” characteristics are often viewed as biological. However, in the post-World War II era racial differences became “inherited and unchangeable” cultural characteristics. While liberal discourses of “assimilation” and “diversity” often call on the racially oppressed to adapt the cultural characteristics of “whites” (“pull yourself up by your own bootstraps”), the structural obstacles to the majority of those constituted as “non-white” to become “respectable” leads to liberal despair about “cultures of poverty.” See Steinberg 1989, Party Two Introduction and Chapter 4 for a discussion of ‘culture’ in racist discourses in the second half of the Twentieth Century.
[53] Virdee 2014 provides an account of “non-color coded” racism in Britain. Roediger 2005 brilliantly charts the shifting boundaries of race among European immigrant workers in the 20th century US.
[54] 1983.
[55] Isaac 2004.
[56] Isaac 2009 p. 42.
[57] Snowden 1983, Chapter 4.
[58] Wood 2003, Chapters 2-3.
[59] 2020 pp. 3-4
[60] I want to thank David Camfield bringing this to my attention.
[61] Herring Tore’s, et al, 2012, and Nirenberg 2009.
[62] Morgan 1975, Fields 1990, Virdee 2018 pp. 11-15. Many Marxists embrace Theodore Allen’s (1995 and 1997) claims in his that racism emerges simultaneously in Colonial Virginia and during the English colonization of Ireland. However, as David Camfield has pointed out in comments on an earlier version of this essay, the oppression of Irish Catholics was not racial—if they converted to Protestantism, they would enjoy the same rights as other Irish Protestants.
[63] Fields 1982 pp. 161-162.
[64] Post 2012, Chapter 3.
[65] Wood 2003, Chapters 4-5; Brenner 1993, Part One.
[66] Omi and Winant 2015.
[67]Fields 1990 pp. 154-155.
[68] Braverman 1974. Unfortunately, most readers of Braverman’s masterpiece tend to equate deskilling with the homogenization of labor. Braverman himself was quite clear that the tendency to deskill work constantlydifferentiates work.
[69] I am deeply indebted to Kim Moody for much of the following.
[70] Virdee 2015, pp. 26-27, 34-37; Virdee 2018, pp. 15-18
[71] Roediger and Esch 2012, Roediger 2005.
[72] Khalili 2020, p. 185.
[73] Brenner and Brenner 1981, p. 31.
[74] Roediger 2019, p. 68.
[75] Ignatiev 1995, Bernstein 2010.
[76] Wolfinger 2009.
[77] Post 2017.
[78] 2014
[79] Chibber 2017.
[80] Goldfield 2020.
[81] Nelson 2001, Chapters 5-7, demonstrates how the CIO’s acceptance of departmental seniority set the stage for the reproduction of racial divisions among steel workers and other organized industrial workers in the post-war period.